26.12.2012 Views

Annals of the History and Philosophy of Biology

Annals of the History and Philosophy of Biology

Annals of the History and Philosophy of Biology

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Was <strong>the</strong>re a Darwinian Revolution?<br />

So, no Darwinian Revolution in this sense. But I still go back to <strong>the</strong> point I made earlier.<br />

I am just not prepared to take <strong>the</strong> present out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> picture. Darwin did get it right<br />

about selection! It took seventy-five years for this to become apparent, but <strong>the</strong>n it did<br />

<strong>and</strong> it has stayed that way. So, if you are prepared to use <strong>the</strong> present as a guide to <strong>the</strong><br />

past – <strong>and</strong> I have defended this practice – so long as you do not gloss over how history<br />

took time to develop, I see no reason to deny Darwin’s role in <strong>the</strong> Darwinian Revolution.<br />

And much good reason to think that <strong>the</strong> revolution is appropriately named.<br />

Was <strong>the</strong>re a Darwinian Revolution?<br />

Here my question is about <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> revolution, meaning more about what kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> revolution it really was. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, my question is more <strong>of</strong> a philosopher’s question,<br />

trying to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> science <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> way in which it changes. The<br />

name <strong>and</strong> work <strong>of</strong> Thomas Kuhn lurks large. So let us phrase <strong>the</strong> question in Kuhnian<br />

terms: Was <strong>the</strong>re a change <strong>of</strong> paradigms in <strong>the</strong> sense described by Thomas Kuhn in his<br />

The Structure <strong>of</strong> Scientific Revolutions? Was <strong>the</strong>re a switch <strong>of</strong> world views – perhaps even a<br />

switch <strong>of</strong> worlds – that required more <strong>of</strong> a leap <strong>of</strong> faith than an appeal to reason? Or was<br />

<strong>the</strong> change smoo<strong>the</strong>r, as more conventional philosophies <strong>of</strong> science might lead one to<br />

expect. Was <strong>the</strong> change more (say) in a Popperian vein, where basically <strong>the</strong> facts told<br />

against <strong>the</strong> older position <strong>and</strong> people shifted because this was <strong>the</strong> reasonable thing to do?<br />

After nearly forty years <strong>of</strong> looking at <strong>the</strong> revolution, my answer is an unequivocal –<br />

yes <strong>and</strong> no (<strong>and</strong> maybe)! At a broad level, <strong>the</strong>re are certainly Kuhnian aspects to <strong>the</strong><br />

revolution. Most strikingly, <strong>the</strong>re were people who simply could not see <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side’s<br />

point <strong>of</strong> view – clever people, that is, who knew <strong>the</strong> ins <strong>and</strong> outs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issues. Most<br />

prominent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se was <strong>the</strong> Swiss-American ichthyologist Louis Agassiz (E. C. Agassiz<br />

1889). He had staked out an idealistic position before <strong>the</strong> Origin (Agassiz 1859) – one<br />

that came directly from his Naturphilosophen teachers (Friedrich Schelling <strong>and</strong> Lorenz<br />

Oken) when he was a student in Munich – <strong>and</strong> try as he might, he could never accept<br />

evolution, even a Germanized form that was being pushed by people like Ernst Haeckel<br />

(1866). To Agassiz’s credit, he really did try – his students around him, including his own<br />

son, were becoming evolutionists in <strong>the</strong> 1860s -- but it was not for him.<br />

Something like this makes perfect sense on <strong>the</strong> Kuhnian scenario <strong>and</strong>, in my opinion,<br />

fits uncomfortably into <strong>the</strong> Popperian (1959) scenario – although in fairness to <strong>the</strong> memory<br />

<strong>of</strong> Popper, I should add that he himself thought that <strong>the</strong> Darwinian Revolution<br />

was more metaphysical than purely science <strong>and</strong> so probably would not think Louis Agassiz<br />

a refutation <strong>of</strong> his position (1974). So let me simply say, without trying to attribute<br />

positions to people, that Agassiz does not fit comfortably into a philosophy <strong>of</strong> science<br />

that makes rational choice <strong>the</strong> sole criterion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory change.<br />

However, in o<strong>the</strong>r respects <strong>the</strong> Darwinian Revolution seems clearly very non-<br />

Kuhnian. There have been major arguments about what precisely Kuhn meant by “different<br />

worlds” – my own inclination is to say, on rereading <strong>the</strong> first edition <strong>of</strong> The Structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> Scientific Revolutions, that Kuhn meant a real ontological change, although tempered<br />

by <strong>the</strong> fact that ontology (in a kind <strong>of</strong> Kantian sense) has to be mediated through <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Annals</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>History</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Philosophy</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Biology</strong>, Vol. 10 (2005)<br />

181

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!