10.07.2015 Views

Great Ideas of Philosophy

Great Ideas of Philosophy

Great Ideas of Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

longer refer merely to this world or even significantly to this world. As for the problem <strong>of</strong> governance, thecity <strong>of</strong> man and the city <strong>of</strong> God are radically different.C. Whatever one takes to be the validity <strong>of</strong> the religious tenets <strong>of</strong> the Christian religion, history teaches thatthe likely success <strong>of</strong> a faith is greatly reduced when it has an <strong>of</strong>ficially anti-intellectual attitude. Asuccessful religion is one that has been promulgated by teaching, rather than by force.D. The anti-intellectualism <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the early fathers <strong>of</strong>ten takes the form <strong>of</strong> quite interesting and pr<strong>of</strong>oundtreatises. As we know, only a person <strong>of</strong> broad learning knows the enemy well enough to mount a worthychallenge. At this juncture enters Augustine, who sets for himself the task <strong>of</strong> recovering the philosophicalwisdom <strong>of</strong> the ancients in order to render it serviceable to the cause <strong>of</strong> Christianity.III. In Greek philosophy, the problem <strong>of</strong> knowledge is settled by rational analysis or as a result <strong>of</strong> some sort <strong>of</strong>intuitive power, or is abandoned as a casualty <strong>of</strong> the Skeptic’s weapons. But as Augustine makes clear in theConfessions, the knowledge sought by the Christian is unattainable without faith, with reason now a secondaryconsideration.A. Augustine writes <strong>of</strong> the ascent toward knowledge made with his mother, Monica, where the ascent itself isimpelled by a sincere love <strong>of</strong> God that allows one to reach planes <strong>of</strong> understanding unreachable by reasonor the arts <strong>of</strong> the metaphysician.B. Man is, as Aristotle teaches, by nature, a social animal. But in the perfectionist moral philosophy <strong>of</strong>Aristotle, there would seem to be little room for the theological virtues <strong>of</strong> faith, hope, and love, which forAugustine, are essential to full development <strong>of</strong> our humanity.C. The ancient philosophers were skeptical about knowing the truth once and for all, and Augustine, too,writes <strong>of</strong> the fallibility <strong>of</strong> human knowledge. But through the grace <strong>of</strong> God, the truth may be gleaned by theunified and immortal soul. As the truths <strong>of</strong> mathematics do not depend on our senses or even ourrationality, there are truths beyond the reach <strong>of</strong> reason, grasped intuitively by some inner light.D. The ancient schools were elitist, utterly incompatible with a vision <strong>of</strong> universal brotherhood, except in therather rationalized version <strong>of</strong> some Stoic philosophy. It is just this brotherhood, however, that is thecornerstone <strong>of</strong> the teachings <strong>of</strong> Christ.E. Unencumbered by a providential monotheistic religion, the pagan world <strong>of</strong> Greek philosophy did not havethat problem <strong>of</strong> evil that plagues the Christian apologists.1. Much that we regard as “evil” arises from our own conduct, prompting us to ask: “Why would Godallow us to do such horrid things?” The stock answer is that we do such things freely and, thus, arefully responsible.2. But if we are free to this degree, then God either could not prevent what we do—and, thus, is notomnipotent—or didn’t know we were going to do it—and, thus, is not omniscient.3. In his treatise on freedom <strong>of</strong> the will, Augustine has two discussants, both <strong>of</strong> whom have faith, take upthis problem. They begin from the premise that God knows everything that is going to happen and iscapable <strong>of</strong> controlling everything. How, then, can the will be free? And if the will isn’t free, how can Ibe held accountable for what I do?4. The Augustinian solution is not entirely successful, as illustrated by the example <strong>of</strong> the traveler: Aguest is forced to switch his means <strong>of</strong> transportation from plane to train but is nonetheless met by hishost, who accurately predicted the guest’s arrival at the train station. To know that an actor will take acertain course is not to strip the actor <strong>of</strong> intentionality.5. From the fact that God knows, in virtue <strong>of</strong> his omniscience, everything that we will do, it does notfollow that when we do it, we do not do it volitionally. The will can be free, and God can knowexactly how it will be exercised.IV. We see in Augustine the introduction <strong>of</strong> a method that will become common in the intellectual history <strong>of</strong> thechurch: an analytical, dialectical approach.A. Consider again the problem <strong>of</strong> knowledge, but this time, the special problem <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> God: Howdo we know about God? On most philosophical accounts, knowledge begins with experience. For theChristian, having accepted that God is an immaterial, massless entity, how can any epistemic claim bemade at all?©2004 The Teaching Company Limited Partnership 17

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!