30.06.2013 Views

How does the operation of PHARMAC's 'Community Exceptional ...

How does the operation of PHARMAC's 'Community Exceptional ...

How does the operation of PHARMAC's 'Community Exceptional ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

that <strong>the</strong> treatment may not be available, and in such circumstances a conscious<br />

decision may be taken by administrators that <strong>the</strong> service is restricted or simply<br />

not <strong>of</strong>fered (Ubel, 2000).<br />

The term ‘rationing’ has also been used to mean societal toleration <strong>of</strong><br />

inequitable access to services deemed necessary, as defined by reference to<br />

appropriate clinical guidelines (Hadorn & Brook, 1991). Early in <strong>the</strong> health<br />

rationing debate, Hadorn (1991) introduced <strong>the</strong> connection between equity and<br />

<strong>the</strong> provision or prohibition <strong>of</strong> needed health services. His central idea was to try<br />

to show what was considered ‘necessary’ and by whom it was considered<br />

‘necessary’. This approach has been challenged by many attempts since 1991<br />

to define <strong>the</strong> term necessary. This has not proved to be simple. Nei<strong>the</strong>r has it<br />

always been easy to be explicit about who benefits from rationed health funds-<br />

<strong>the</strong> patients, <strong>the</strong> doctors and staff, <strong>the</strong> service owners or <strong>the</strong> funders.<br />

There are, however o<strong>the</strong>r ways <strong>of</strong> thinking about what health care provision<br />

might be considered necessary and unnecessary. Malin, Wilmot, and<br />

Manthorpe (2002) divided <strong>the</strong> elements <strong>of</strong> distributive justice relating to <strong>the</strong><br />

fairness <strong>of</strong> distributing health care into four areas: need, rights, desert and<br />

utility. I present <strong>the</strong>se four categories here. Need was described as <strong>the</strong> ability<br />

to benefit from a treatment and is associated with <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> severity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

condition and <strong>the</strong> effectiveness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> remedy. <strong>How</strong>ever, this is problematic<br />

because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> layers <strong>of</strong> need. Malin et al. point out that a person<br />

may need a pair <strong>of</strong> shoes or we could say <strong>the</strong>y need education and up-skilling<br />

to be able to enter <strong>the</strong> labour market to earn enough income to buy a pair <strong>of</strong><br />

shoes. There appears no obvious method <strong>of</strong> analysing needs and efficiency in<br />

such terms.<br />

The second element <strong>of</strong> distributive justice described by Malin et al. (2002) is<br />

rights. Two types <strong>of</strong> rights are described. Firstly ‘ideal’ rights which are claimed<br />

on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> general moral principles and stand independently and prior to<br />

laws as ideal arrangements for human societies. This too is problematic<br />

because <strong>the</strong> exercise <strong>of</strong> such rights in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> right to life or <strong>the</strong> right to<br />

adequate health care is generally determined by access to adequate resources.<br />

Therefore, <strong>the</strong> gatekeeper who provides such access has power over <strong>the</strong> rights<br />

18

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!