28.01.2015 Views

BENEDICT DE SPINOZA: Theological-Political Treatise

BENEDICT DE SPINOZA: Theological-Political Treatise

BENEDICT DE SPINOZA: Theological-Political Treatise

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Theological</strong>-<strong>Political</strong> <strong>Treatise</strong><br />

They would, however, have had no hope of achieving this had they<br />

con¢ned themselves only to the promptings of desire ^ for, by the laws of<br />

appetite, everyone is drawn in di¡erent directions.Thus, they had to make<br />

a ¢rm decision, and reach agreement, to decide everything by the sole<br />

dictate of reason (which no one dares contradict openly for fear of appearing<br />

perfectly mindless). They had to curb their appetites so far as their<br />

desires suggested things which would hurt someone else, and refrain from<br />

doing anything to anyone they did not want done to themselves. Finally,<br />

they were obliged to defend other people’s rights as their own.<br />

[6] Now we must consider how this agreement has to be made if it is to<br />

be accepted and endure. For it is a universal law of human nature that no<br />

one neglects anything that they deem good unless they hope for a greater<br />

192 good or fear a greater loss, and no one puts up with anything bad except<br />

to avoid something worse or because he hopes for something better.<br />

That is, of two good things every single person will choose the one<br />

which he himself judges to be the greater good, and of two bad things he<br />

will choose that which he deems to be less bad. 3 I say expressly what<br />

appears to him the greater or lesser good when he makes this choice,<br />

since the real situation is not necessarily as he judges it to be. This law is<br />

so ¢rmly inscribed in human nature that it may be included among the<br />

eternal truths that no one can fail to know. It necessarily follows that no<br />

one will promise without deception 4 to give up his right to all things,<br />

and absolutely no one will keep his promises except from fear of a greater<br />

ill or hope of a greater good.<br />

To understand this better, imagine that a highwayman forces me to<br />

promise to give him all I have, at his demand. Since my natural right is<br />

determined by my power alone, as I have already shown, it is certain that if<br />

I can free myself from him by deceit, by promising whatever he wants,<br />

I may by the law of nature do so, i.e., I may fraudulently agree to whatever<br />

he demands. Or suppose that I have made a promise to someone in good<br />

faith not to taste food or any sustenance for a space of twenty days and only<br />

later realize that my promise was stupid and that I cannot keep it without<br />

doing myself a great deal of harm. Since I am obliged by natural right to<br />

choose the lesser of two evils, I have a sovereign right to break the bond of<br />

3 This doctrine, developed more fully in Spinoza’s Ethics, functions consistently throughout his work<br />

as a fundamental principle of his psychology, his moral philosophy and his political thought.<br />

4 Spinoza’s footnote: see Annotation 32.<br />

198

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!