10.07.2015 Views

Work and Leisure

Work and Leisure

Work and Leisure

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Gender, work <strong>and</strong> leisure 71<strong>and</strong> they exist alongside each other (Stanley <strong>and</strong> Wise 1993: 191; Maynard<strong>and</strong> Purvis 1994: 19).Feminist empiricists emerged from the 1960s ‘liberal tendency’ whichhoped <strong>and</strong> believed that it would be possible to engage traditional epistemologistswith changes by using reason <strong>and</strong> logic in ways similar to theirs, toshow not only that there could be several worldviews but also that these couldbe measured, <strong>and</strong> so new types of knowledge could be acknowledged <strong>and</strong>given status. The belief that debate, the use of rigorous research methods, <strong>and</strong>common sense would sway the traditionalists was, in retrospect, naive. It alsounderestimated the power of rationality, the criteria used for the reception<strong>and</strong> acknowledgement of knowledge <strong>and</strong>, simply, the deep suspicion of anyknowledge which was seemingly grounded in gender. The difficulties for liberalempiricists were compounded in the 1970s by the scarcity of women inthe academy, <strong>and</strong> the multiple campaigns with which they were involved;there was too much to do <strong>and</strong> neither enough time or resources with which todo it. This was as true of leisure studies as any other field. It had been defined<strong>and</strong> dominated by men, who had invented <strong>and</strong> sustained the ‘work–leisure’divide as it fitted their experience <strong>and</strong> seemingly kept them in a dominantposition. It is notable that only one chapter out of thirteen in the 1975volume <strong>Work</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Leisure</strong>, which the current volume celebrates, was by awoman (Emmett 1975). Feminist academics recognised this world but knew itwas not theirs.St<strong>and</strong>point epistemologists have tried to explain the impact <strong>and</strong> effect ofdifferent value systems on knowledge; they have seen a need to work with <strong>and</strong>articulate the views of those groups of women who have been marginalisedby the dominant groups of women who have tended to be more like thedominant groups of men in the liberal empiricist tradition: white, middleclass,heterosexual intellectuals. St<strong>and</strong>point epistemologies argued that forfeminism to have any acceptability it had to recognise the diverse <strong>and</strong> differingst<strong>and</strong>points of different women, accepting <strong>and</strong> celebrating these <strong>and</strong>incorporating them into knowledge <strong>and</strong> common, conflicting, or contrastingst<strong>and</strong>points (Harding 1993: 56). Harding saw this as a ‘strong objectivity’,demonstrating the essential social ‘situatedness’ of beliefs <strong>and</strong> thoughtswhich could be used to develop analysis <strong>and</strong> policy in ways not dissimilar tothose used by ‘objective scientists.’ Although Stanley <strong>and</strong> Wise (1993)applauded the concept, which allowed diversity to be acknowledged throughembracing a variety of feminist viewpoints, they were worried about itspotential ethnocentricity.More recently, feminist postmodern theorists have adapted a Foucauldianapproach, the argument being that, as power resides within individuals, eachof us has the opportunity to create our own distinctive knowledges, which areuniquely our own <strong>and</strong> not rule-bound by tradition (Wearing 1998; Aitchison2000). Attractive as this may be, <strong>and</strong> despite its potential to empower individualsin ways which are not otherwise available, there are concerns about its

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!