17.06.2013 Views

Untitled

Untitled

Untitled

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

140 Chapter 3<br />

sense, when a man marries a second time during his first wife’s<br />

lifetime, so that the second marriage is invalid. Another situation<br />

listed is that of a man in holy orders (probably he means a subdeacon<br />

or someone of higher rank) who marries a woman who is not a<br />

virgin. In this case the marriage is null. It would in fact have been<br />

null even if the woman were a virgin. After 1139 it was clear law<br />

that the marriage of a cleric in major orders (a subdeacon, deacon,<br />

or priest) was not only illicit but also invalid. So why does John<br />

raise the case in the context of ‘bigamy’ and what di·erence does it<br />

make whether the woman was a virgin?<br />

The fact that the woman is not a virgin may have been introduced<br />

by Johannes because a rigorist understanding of ‘bigamy’<br />

sometimes included marriages to women who had previously slept<br />

with another man, whether or not they were widows. Reading between<br />

the lines, John’s point may be this: if a priest invalidly marries<br />

a virgin, he can after separating from the woman and undergoing<br />

a long penance obtain a dispensation from a bishop to resume his<br />

priestly oce. On the other hand, if the woman had not been a<br />

virgin, an episcopal dispensation would not be enough, because<br />

the sexual union had been akin to bigamy, bigamy by extension so<br />

to speak.<br />

A casuistry of bigamy and its implications<br />

If we take Innocent III’s decretal Debitum and Johannes de Deo’s<br />

analysis together, an important conclusion about the social relevance<br />

of marriage symbolism begins to emerge. The rationality of<br />

marriage symbolism was the basis of a casuistry of ‘bigamy’ cases,<br />

providing the principles that could enable discrimination between<br />

apparently similar cases and settle the law when its application<br />

to ambiguous instances was unobvious. Incidentally, we have here<br />

a criterion for distinguishing between unthinking ‘tradition’ and<br />

‘value rationality’ as determinants of social action. Value rationality<br />

is not just about general principles, far from it, but they are an<br />

important element, and can be invoked and applied by casuistry to<br />

settle ambiguous concrete cases. Tradition alone could not provide<br />

such a casuistry. Its social relevance was confined to men who had<br />

been married and widowed.<br />

The remainder of this chapter deals with people who did not seek<br />

to become priests. Section (b) deals with second weddings, and the<br />

final section with married clerics in minor orders. In neither case

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!