20.07.2013 Views

Beyond Time - Linguistics - University of California, Berkeley

Beyond Time - Linguistics - University of California, Berkeley

Beyond Time - Linguistics - University of California, Berkeley

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

not on the day <strong>of</strong> perspective time. Neither <strong>of</strong> these necessarily requires extension <strong>of</strong> the<br />

domain <strong>of</strong> perspective time beyond hodiernality, since the situations’ effects (i.e. states<br />

<strong>of</strong> nuclear completion), or their (virtual) onsets overlap with the day <strong>of</strong> perspective time.<br />

Conversely, use <strong>of</strong> -ka- and na- excludes the discourse content from the day <strong>of</strong> perspective<br />

time. Use <strong>of</strong> -ka- or na- for situations within that domain therefore creates a clash and<br />

remains infelicitous.<br />

It may also be noted that use <strong>of</strong> prehodiernal -ka- for hodiernal situations would result in<br />

homophony with distal -ka-, discussed in the next paragraph. In any case, the distribution<br />

<strong>of</strong> -ka- and na- in Totela is not incompatible with an analysis <strong>of</strong> dissociativity. 14<br />

The asymmetry in the optionality these markers in Totela, along with that <strong>of</strong> possibly<br />

similar systems in other languages, deserves detailed cross-linguistic investigation, particularly<br />

with respect to its pathway <strong>of</strong> development: Does temporal rigidity develop first and<br />

then loosen (expected if markers grammaticalize from temporal adverbs), or does temporal<br />

rigidity develop out <strong>of</strong> originally subjective temporal distance marking (expected, perhaps,<br />

if markers grammaticalize from distal markers)?<br />

Further evidence for dissociativity <strong>of</strong> -ka- and na- may be found found in morphology.<br />

Strikingly, as noted in 5.3.1.1, the morpheme that marks spatial distance from the discourse<br />

reference point is formally identical to prehodiernal -ka- (see examples (270) to (269) above).<br />

Recall that Botne & Kershner (2008) list three kinds <strong>of</strong> dissociation: temporal, spatial,<br />

14 It should be noted that, somewhat surprisingly, hodiernal past statives and especially -ite forms with<br />

change-<strong>of</strong>-state verbs are negated with prehodiernal ka- when used imperfectively, as in (1). Example (2)<br />

shows that -ite forms cannot be used with past -na-. In (1c), then, a prehodiernal form is recruited to<br />

fill a morphological gap. Section 7.3.1 discusses further the use <strong>of</strong> imperfective ka- with hodiernal states,<br />

suggesting that its use in such contexts may be related to the expected permanence <strong>of</strong> states.<br />

(1) a. ndìnàtábà<br />

ndi-na-tab-a<br />

1sg-pst-become.happy-fv<br />

‘I was happy’ (earlier today) (ZT2009Elic122)<br />

b. *kanditabite sunu<br />

*ka-ndi-tab-ite<br />

sunu<br />

prehod.ipfv-1sg-become.happy-ite today<br />

(intended): ‘I was happy today’ (ZT2009Elic122)<br />

c. tàkándìtàbìté sùnù<br />

ta-ka-ndi-tab-ite<br />

sunu<br />

neg-prehod.ipfv-1sg-become.happy-ite today<br />

‘I wasn’t happy today’ (ZT2009Elic122)<br />

(2) *ndinachisitwe<br />

*ndi-na-tab-it-w-e<br />

1sg-pst-hurt-ite-pass-ite<br />

(intended) ‘I was sick’ (earlier today) (ZT2009Elic34)<br />

226

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!