10.04.2014 Views

Conservation and Sustainable Use of the Biosphere - WBGU

Conservation and Sustainable Use of the Biosphere - WBGU

Conservation and Sustainable Use of the Biosphere - WBGU

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Fundamentals <strong>of</strong> environmental ethics<br />

H 3<br />

In our dealings with <strong>the</strong> environment, <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

basic <strong>and</strong> human rights, as well as <strong>the</strong> civil rights that<br />

have in some cases been derived from <strong>the</strong>m, should<br />

be just as much a foundation <strong>of</strong> our considerations as<br />

in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r areas <strong>of</strong> application <strong>of</strong> ethics. However,<br />

with regard to <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> principles, <strong>the</strong>re is a special<br />

problem relating to <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

environment: does <strong>the</strong> basic postulate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sustenance<br />

<strong>of</strong> life apply exclusively to human beings or<br />

also to all o<strong>the</strong>r beings? This question does not lead<br />

to a new primary principle, as one may suspect at first<br />

glance. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is necessary to delineate <strong>the</strong> universally<br />

accepted principle <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sustenance <strong>of</strong> life that<br />

has already been laid down in <strong>the</strong> body <strong>of</strong> basic<br />

rights. Does this principle cover only human beings<br />

(this is <strong>the</strong> codified version valid in most legal constitutions<br />

today) or also o<strong>the</strong>r living creatures? And if<br />

so, which ones?<br />

Should inanimate elements be included too? In<br />

answering this question, it is at first possible to take<br />

up two contradictory positions: anthropocentrism<br />

<strong>and</strong> physiocentrism (Taylor, 1986; Ott, 1993; Galert,<br />

1998). The anthropocentric view places humankind<br />

<strong>and</strong> its needs at <strong>the</strong> fore. Nature’s own fundamental<br />

rights are alien to this view. Interventions in nature<br />

are allowed if <strong>the</strong>y are useful to humankind. A duty<br />

to make provision for <strong>the</strong> future <strong>and</strong> to conserve<br />

nature exists in <strong>the</strong> anthropocentric view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world<br />

only to <strong>the</strong> extent that natural systems are classed as<br />

valuable to humankind <strong>and</strong> that nature can be<br />

regarded as <strong>the</strong> means <strong>and</strong> guarantor <strong>of</strong> human life<br />

<strong>and</strong> survival (Norton, 1987; Birnbacher, 1991b).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> physiocentric concept, which forms an<br />

opposite pole to <strong>the</strong> anthropocentric view, <strong>the</strong> needs<br />

<strong>of</strong> humankind are not placed above those <strong>of</strong> nature.<br />

Here, every living being, whe<strong>the</strong>r human, animal or<br />

plant, has <strong>the</strong> same rights with regard to <strong>the</strong> basic<br />

opportunity to develop its own life within <strong>the</strong> framework<br />

<strong>of</strong> a natural order. In <strong>the</strong> physiocentric view,<br />

worthiness <strong>of</strong> protection stems from an inner value<br />

that is unique to each living being. Nature has an<br />

intrinsic value that does not depend on <strong>the</strong> functions<br />

that it presently fulfils or might later fulfil from<br />

humankind’s point <strong>of</strong> view (Devall <strong>and</strong> Sessions,<br />

1984; Naess, 1986; Callicott, 1989; Meyer-Abich, 1996;<br />

Rolston, 1994b).<br />

Where <strong>the</strong> issues <strong>of</strong> environmental design <strong>and</strong><br />

environmental policy are concerned, anthropocentric<br />

<strong>and</strong> physiocentric approaches in <strong>the</strong>ir pure form<br />

are found only rarely; ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y occur in different<br />

mixtures <strong>and</strong> slants.The transitions between <strong>the</strong> concepts<br />

are fluid. Moderate approaches certainly take<br />

on elements from <strong>the</strong> opposite position. It may thus<br />

be in line with a fundamentally physiocentric perspective<br />

if <strong>the</strong> priority <strong>of</strong> human interests is not<br />

called into question in <strong>the</strong> conflict over resources. It<br />

is also true that <strong>the</strong> conclusions <strong>of</strong> a moderate form<br />

<strong>of</strong> anthropocentrism may approach <strong>the</strong> implications<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> physiocentric view. The recommendations for<br />

action <strong>of</strong> a protectionist form <strong>of</strong> anthropocentrism,<br />

which sees nature as an object to be protected against<br />

human intervention <strong>and</strong> uses an existential value <strong>of</strong><br />

nature desired by humankind beyond <strong>the</strong> conservation<br />

<strong>of</strong> resources, will not be far removed from those<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> physiocentric view.<br />

If we look at <strong>the</strong> behaviour patterns <strong>of</strong> people in<br />

different cultures, physiocentric or anthropocentric<br />

basic positions are rarely maintained consistently<br />

(Bargatzky <strong>and</strong> Kuschel, 1994; on <strong>the</strong> convergence<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory Birnbacher, 1996). In <strong>the</strong> strongly anthropocentric<br />

countries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> West, people spend more<br />

money on <strong>the</strong> welfare <strong>and</strong> health <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own pets<br />

than on saving human lives in o<strong>the</strong>r countries; in <strong>the</strong><br />

countries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Far East that are characterized by<br />

physiocentrism, nature is frequently exploited even<br />

more radically than in <strong>the</strong> industrialized countries <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> West. This inconsistency is not a justification for<br />

one view or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, it is just a warning for caution<br />

when laying down fur<strong>the</strong>r rules for use so that no<br />

extreme – <strong>and</strong> thus untenable – dem<strong>and</strong>s be made.<br />

Also from an ethical point <strong>of</strong> view, radical anthropocentrism<br />

should be rejected just as much as radical<br />

physiocentrism. If, to take up just one argument here,<br />

<strong>the</strong> right to human safety is largely justified by <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that <strong>the</strong> causing <strong>of</strong> pain by o<strong>the</strong>rs should be seen<br />

as something to be avoided, this consideration without<br />

doubt has to be applied to o<strong>the</strong>r beings that are<br />

also capable <strong>of</strong> feeling pain (referred to as: patho-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!