04.06.2014 Views

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

112 Chapter 4<br />

the wellbeing of all its members. An act is just only if it maximises the<br />

wellbeing of everyone else. 42<br />

From a utilitarian perspective, the law and the courts have very<br />

important roles to play in the enterprise of realising social cooperation.<br />

In terms of this view, courts have to consider interests<br />

other than those of the parties before them. In this context, actions,<br />

policies, and institutions are judged in terms of the extent to which<br />

they maximise overall happiness and wellbeing. 43 It is this form of<br />

justice that persons such as Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart sought<br />

to entrench in England in the nineteenth century. They viewed the<br />

laws that existed then as morally atrocious because they prevented<br />

rather than promoted overall happiness. 44 Utilitarianism also<br />

represents itself in the form of what has been described as<br />

communitarianism, a concept which challenges libertarianism on the<br />

grounds that an individual is not an end, but exists together with<br />

others with whom he or she pursues a common end. 45 Communitarians<br />

submit that an ideal society is one that defines the individual in terms<br />

of what they are and the values that they have. 46<br />

Unlike bilateral corrective justice, distributive justice is therefore<br />

multilateral. Justice from this perspective is the standard by which<br />

conflicting values are reconciled and competing conceptions of good<br />

accommodated or resolved. 47 Though a court case may have only two<br />

parties, distributive justice views it as having community-wide<br />

implications. As a result, the court focuses on what Cooper-<br />

Stephenson has described as collateral interests that need secondary<br />

consideration. 48 This has arisen from the recognition that not all<br />

interested persons may be party to a suit, and yet their interests may<br />

be affected by the outcome of that suit. 49 While corrective justice<br />

42 See P Vallentyne Distributive justice, sourced at http://www.missouri.edu/<br />

~klinechair/on-line%20papers/distributive%20justice%20(handbook).doc<br />

(accessed 24 June 2006). See also J Rawls Political liberalism (1993) 16; and S<br />

Scheffler ‘Rawls and utilitarianism’ in S Freeman (ed) The Cambridge companion<br />

to Rawls (2003) 426.<br />

43 Wellman (n 8 above) 60.<br />

44 Wellman (n 8 above) 61.<br />

45<br />

See S Mulhall & A Swift Liberals and communitarians (1996) 10. See also generally<br />

W Kymlicka ‘Community’ in E Goodin & P Pettit (eds) A companion to<br />

contemporary political philosophy (1995) 366; and M Scanlon What we owe each<br />

other (2000).<br />

46 Mulhall & Swift (n 45 above) 13.<br />

47 Sandel (n 5 above) 16.<br />

48<br />

Cooper-Stephenson (n 17 above) 19.<br />

49 Cooper-Stephenson (n 17 above) 19 submits that it has also arisen from the<br />

increased focus which is being given to the deterrent effect of remedies, which<br />

requires consideration of the interests of the future community of persons who<br />

will find themselves in a like situation as the plaintiff and defendant.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!