04.06.2014 Views

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

76 Chapter 3<br />

behind the protection of human rights’. 100 While this approach<br />

realises socio-economic rights and gives them content as individual<br />

rights; situating the minimum core solely in subsection (1) fails to<br />

integrate the inadequacy of resources as a possible defence for failure<br />

to satisfy the minimum core obligations. 101<br />

As indicated above, a country can rely on inadequacy of resources<br />

to justify its failure to meet the minimum core obligations. 102 Reading<br />

the sections as proposed above suggests that the limitations in<br />

subsection (2), including inadequacy of resources, would only apply at<br />

the second level of progressive improvements from the minimum<br />

core. This means that if resource limitations are to be invoked as a<br />

defence, then this has to be derived from the notion of minimum core<br />

itself and not subsection (2). However, this is problematic: Since<br />

inadequacy of resources is expressly integrated in the Constitution, it<br />

would only be logical for this defence to derive from subsection (2).<br />

One would argue, though, that interpreting subsections (1) and (2)<br />

holistically would subject the minimum core to the notion of<br />

progressive realisation, thereby denying it meaning. However, this<br />

argument does not stand since the minimum core itself derives from<br />

the notion of progressive realisation. 103<br />

The minimum core approach stresses the point that, in spite of the<br />

fact that countries may realise the rights progressively, certain<br />

obligations have to be met immediately as a matter of priority. 104 It<br />

also emphasises the point that if the core content is not provided,<br />

irrespective of progressive realisation and acting within available<br />

resources, the rights would be rendered useless. On the basis of this,<br />

therefore, the minimum core can only be derived from reading<br />

subsection (1) together with (2), and not to isolate one from<br />

100 Bilchitz (n 34 above) 12. Bilchitz contends further that sects 26 and 27 protect<br />

two kinds of interests which are linked by the notion of progressive realisation.<br />

The first is that, at a minimum level, people need to survive and for this they<br />

require basic goods and services; the second is the interest that people have in<br />

being provided with the conditions that enable them to pursue their own projects<br />

and live a good life by their own rights (10-11).<br />

101 As discussed in the next section, this reading was rejected by the Constitutional<br />

Court in the TAC case.<br />

102 See also Pieterse (n 56 above) 480.<br />

103 Though not expressly, Bilchitz (n 58 above) 56A-36, appears to have abandoned<br />

his initial suggestions that the two subsections be read as giving rise to two<br />

different and self-standing obligations. He has submitted that the notion of<br />

progressive realisation should be read as involving two components: The first<br />

component is a minimum core, to realise, as a matter of priority, the minimally<br />

adequate provision required to meet basic needs; the second component is the<br />

duty to take steps to improve the adequacy of the provisions of resources over<br />

time.<br />

104 Chapman & Russell (n 44 above) 6.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!