04.06.2014 Views

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

122 Chapter 4<br />

government that bears the obligation that has been violated. This is<br />

not possible where the court ignores the character of the defendant<br />

and the nature of the obligations of that defendant.<br />

4.3 Relationship between rights and remedies<br />

The relationship of rights and remedies has been the subject of<br />

controversy between scholars for quite some time. While some<br />

scholars believe that rights and remedies are interlinked, others insist<br />

that the two should be de-linked and considered separately. It is<br />

worthwhile exploring this debate because of its impact on the kinds<br />

of remedies that a court may grant and its relationship with the ethos<br />

of justice. The relationship that different scholars ascribe to rights<br />

and remedies has, amongst others, been determined by the notion of<br />

justice to which they subscribe. Linkage between rights and remedies<br />

makes sense from the perspective of the theory of corrective justice.<br />

This is because remedies under this theory of justice are supposed to<br />

restore the right in its entirety.<br />

A judge who believes in the linkage between rights and remedies<br />

will therefore restrict himself or herself to those remedies that<br />

maximise the right and will not pay attention to considerations not<br />

connected to the right, even if these impact on the implementation<br />

of the remedy. This is the basis of the theory that the only reason<br />

remedies exist is to serve to implement substantive rights, and that<br />

the remedy should, as far as possible, serve to vindicate the right in<br />

issue. 97 This approach is in accordance with the concept of rights<br />

maximisation which requires that the only question that a court asks<br />

after finding that there is a violation is one of which remedies will be<br />

most effective to the victims. 98 Considerations such as the costs of<br />

the remedy, unless they impact on the effectiveness of the remedy,<br />

are irrelevant.<br />

Distributive justice, on the other hand, supports the de-linking of<br />

right and remedy. This is because this form of justice allows judges,<br />

when choosing a remedy, to take into account factors that may not<br />

necessarily relate to the nature or objects of the rights. This view is<br />

supported by a number of scholars. 99 It is contended by some scholars<br />

that rights are idealistic and can exist on their own. However, they<br />

need to be transformed into reality by the use of remedies. It is for<br />

this reason that Fiss submits that rights and remedies are but two<br />

97 Cooper-Stephenson (n 17 above) 5.<br />

98<br />

See generally Gewirtz (n 75 above).<br />

99 See O Fiss ‘Foreword: The forms of justice’ (1979) 93 Harvard Law Review 1; F<br />

Sager ‘Fair measure: The legal status of underenforced constitutional norms’<br />

(1978) 91 Harvard Law Review 1212; D Walker The law of civil remedies in<br />

Scotland (1974); and Sturm (n 31 above).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!