04.06.2014 Views

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

LITIGATING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN SOUTH AFRICA - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Translating socio-economic rights 81<br />

The question, however, is whether the reasonableness review<br />

approach is an administrative law approach, as has been<br />

suggested. 123 As is demonstrated later, the reasonableness review<br />

approach has established standards of scrutiny that are quite<br />

different from those established by administrative law. 124<br />

According to Fredman, in an administrative law case an agency<br />

has a duty of accountability, which means that it must explain why it<br />

has adopted a particular allocation of resources and not another. 125<br />

In such a case, the duty of the court becomes one of guarding against<br />

arbitrariness in resource allocation. 126 The burden imposed on the<br />

state in this case would be one of justification. In the context of<br />

sections 26 and 27, the state would have to justify its programmes as<br />

reasonable and undertaken ‘within the available resources’. This<br />

approach is akin to what was suggested by Mureinik as to how the Bill<br />

of Rights could be reviewed to quell fears that judicial review is<br />

countermajoritarian. 127 Mureinik’s suggested approach was intended<br />

to ensure that government decisions are rational, while at the same<br />

time restricting the court’s intrusiveness by allowing the state a wide<br />

margin of discretion. Mureinik suggested that all that the state would<br />

have to do was to justify its decisions; such decisions would only be<br />

struck down by the court if the state ‘could not offer a plausible<br />

justification for the programme it has chosen’. 128 Mureinik contended<br />

that ‘any decision maker who is aware … of the risk of being required<br />

to justify a decision will always consider it more closely than if there<br />

was no risk’. 129<br />

Mureinik’s form of constitutional review fares partly in the<br />

Soobramoney case. In this case, the Constitutional Court held that it<br />

‘will be slow to interfere with rational decisions taken in good faith<br />

123 See C Sunstein Designing democracy: What constitutions do (2001) 224. See also<br />

Bilchitz (n 81 above) 56A-11.<br />

124<br />

See Wesson (n 50 above) 287; and Steinberg (n 13 above) 277.<br />

125 S Fredman ‘Providing equality: Substantive equality and the positive duty to<br />

provide’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 163 176. See also Davis<br />

(n 9 above) 304.<br />

126 Sunstein (n 123 above) 224-37.<br />

127 E Mureinik ‘Beyond a charter of luxuries: Economic rights in the Constitution’<br />

(1992) 8 South African Journal on Human Rights 464.<br />

128 Mureinik (n 127 above) 471. In a subsequent article, Mureinik describes the new<br />

constitutional order as a bridge from a culture of authoritarianism, that<br />

characterised apartheid, to a culture of justification; a culture in which every<br />

exercise of public power is supposed to be justified. E Mureinik ‘A bridge to<br />

where? Introduction to the interim Bill of Rights’ (1994) 10 South African Journal<br />

on Human Rights 31. See also generally K Karl ‘Legal culture and transformative<br />

constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 South African Journal of Human Rights 147.<br />

129 Mureinik (n 127 above) 471. He submits that such decision maker is put under<br />

pressure consciously to consider and meet all the objections and thoughtfully to<br />

discard all the alternatives to the decision contemplated.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!