21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

204 BIOLOGY IS ENGINEERING Original Sin <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Birth <strong>of</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> 205<br />

counts as a canonical version <strong>of</strong> anything. That is, although we can identify<br />

mutations by simply comparing <strong>the</strong> "before" sequence with <strong>the</strong> "after"<br />

sequence, <strong>the</strong>re is no intrinsic way <strong>of</strong> telling which <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> uncorrected<br />

typographical errors might more fruitfully be viewed as editorial improvements.<br />

9 Most mutations are what engineers would call "don't-cares," variations<br />

that make no discernible difference to viability, but as selection<br />

gradually takes its toll, <strong>the</strong> better versions begin to cluster. It is only relative<br />

to a "wild type" (a center <strong>of</strong> gravity, in effect, <strong>of</strong> such a cluster) that we can<br />

identify a particular version as a mistaken version, <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong><br />

possibility, remote in practice but omnipresent in principle, that what seems a<br />

mistake from <strong>the</strong> perspective <strong>of</strong> one wild type is a brilliant improvement from<br />

<strong>the</strong> perspective <strong>of</strong> a wild-type-in-<strong>the</strong>-making. And as new wild types emerge<br />

as <strong>the</strong> foci or summits <strong>of</strong> fitness l<strong>and</strong>scapes, <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> steady<br />

pressure <strong>of</strong> error correction can reverse in any particular neighborhood <strong>of</strong><br />

Design Space. Once a particular family <strong>of</strong> similar texts is no longer subject to<br />

"correction" relative to a receding or lapsed norm, it is free to w<strong>and</strong>er into <strong>the</strong><br />

attractive basin <strong>of</strong> a new norm. 10 Reproductive isolation is thus both a cause<br />

<strong>and</strong> an effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> clumpiness <strong>of</strong> phenotypic space. Wherever <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

competing error-correcting regimes, one regime or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r will win out, <strong>and</strong><br />

hence <strong>the</strong> isthmus between <strong>the</strong> competitors will tend to dissolve, leaving<br />

empty space between occupied zones <strong>of</strong> Design Space. Thus, just as norms <strong>of</strong><br />

pronunciation <strong>and</strong> word use reinforce clustering in speech communities (a<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretically important point made by Quine 1960 in his discussion <strong>of</strong> error<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> norms in language ), so norms <strong>of</strong> genomic expression<br />

are <strong>the</strong> ultimate basis <strong>of</strong> speci-ation.<br />

Through <strong>the</strong> same molecular-level microscope we see <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> meaning,<br />

in <strong>the</strong> acquisition <strong>of</strong> "semantics'' by <strong>the</strong> nucleotide sequences, which at first<br />

are mere syntactic objects. This is a crucial step in <strong>the</strong> Darwinian campaign<br />

to overthrow John Locke's Mind-first vision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cosmos. Philosophers<br />

commonly agree, for good reason, that meaning <strong>and</strong> mind can<br />

9. Note <strong>the</strong> parallel here with my discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> false dichotomy between Orwellian<br />

<strong>and</strong> Stalinesque models <strong>of</strong> consciousness in Consciousness Explained (1991a). In that<br />

case as well, <strong>the</strong>re is no intrinsic mark <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> canonical.<br />

10. Once again we see <strong>the</strong> tolerance for topsy-turvy imagery. Some <strong>the</strong>orists speak <strong>of</strong><br />

basins <strong>of</strong> attraction, guided by <strong>the</strong> metaphor <strong>of</strong> balls rolling blindly downhill to <strong>the</strong> local<br />

minimum instead <strong>of</strong> climbing blindly uphill to <strong>the</strong> local maximum. Just turn an adaptive<br />

l<strong>and</strong>scape inside out <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> mountains become basins, <strong>the</strong> ridges become canyons, <strong>and</strong><br />

"gravity" provides <strong>the</strong> analogue <strong>of</strong> selection pressure. It doesn't make any difference<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r you choose "up" or "down" as <strong>the</strong> favored direction, just so long as you are<br />

consistent. Here I have slipped, momentarily, into <strong>the</strong> rival perspective, just to make this<br />

point.<br />

never be pulled apart, that <strong>the</strong>re could never be meaning where <strong>the</strong>re was no<br />

mind, or mind where <strong>the</strong>re was no meaning. Intentionality is <strong>the</strong> philosopher's<br />

technical term for this meaning; it is <strong>the</strong> "aboutness" that can relate<br />

one thing to ano<strong>the</strong>r—a name to its bearer, an alarm call to <strong>the</strong> danger that<br />

triggered it, a word to its referent, a thought to its object. 11 Only some things<br />

in <strong>the</strong> universe manifest intentionality. A book or a painting can be about a<br />

mountain, but a mountain itself is not about anything. A map or a sign or a<br />

dream or a song can be about Paris, but Paris is not about anything.<br />

Intentionality is widely regarded by philosophers as <strong>the</strong> mark <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mental.<br />

Where does intentionality come from? It comes from minds, <strong>of</strong> course.<br />

But that idea, perfectly good in its own way, becomes a source <strong>of</strong> mystery<br />

<strong>and</strong> confusion when it is used as a metaphysical principle, ra<strong>the</strong>r than a fact<br />

<strong>of</strong> recent natural history. Aristotle called God <strong>the</strong> Unmoved Mover, <strong>the</strong><br />

source <strong>of</strong> all motion in <strong>the</strong> universe, <strong>and</strong> Locke's version <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian<br />

doctrine, as we have seen, identifies this God as Mind, turning <strong>the</strong> Unmoved<br />

Mover into <strong>the</strong> Unmeant Meaner, <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> all Intentionality. Locke took<br />

himself to be proving deductively what <strong>the</strong> tradition already took to be<br />

obvious: original intentionality springs from <strong>the</strong> Mind <strong>of</strong> God; we are God's<br />

creatures, <strong>and</strong> derive our intentionality from Him.<br />

Darwin turned this doctrine upside down: intentionality doesn't come from<br />

on high; it percolates up from below, from <strong>the</strong> initially mindless <strong>and</strong> pointless<br />

algorithmic processes that gradually acquire meaning <strong>and</strong> intelligence as <strong>the</strong>y<br />

develop. And, perfectly following <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> all Darwinian thinking, we<br />

see that <strong>the</strong> first meaning is not full-fledged meaning; it certainly fails to<br />

manifest all <strong>the</strong> "essential" properties <strong>of</strong> real meaning (whatever you may<br />

take those properties to be). It is mere quasi-meaning, or semi-semantics. It is<br />

what John Searle (1980,1985,1992 ) has disparaged as mere "as if<br />

intentionality" as opposed to what he calls "Original Intentionality." But you<br />

have to start somewhere, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> first step in <strong>the</strong> right direction is<br />

just barely discernible as a step towards meaning at all is just what we should<br />

expect.<br />

There are two paths to intentionality. The Darwinian path is diachronic, or<br />

historical, <strong>and</strong> concerns <strong>the</strong> gradual accretion, over billions <strong>of</strong> years, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

sorts <strong>of</strong> Design—<strong>of</strong> functionality <strong>and</strong> purposiveness—that can support an<br />

intentional interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> activities <strong>of</strong> organisms (<strong>the</strong> "doings" <strong>of</strong><br />

"agents"). Before intentionality can be fully fledged, it must go through its<br />

awkward, ugly period <strong>of</strong> fea<strong>the</strong>rless pseudo-intentionality. The synchronic<br />

11. The topic <strong>of</strong> intentionality has been written about extensively by philosophers <strong>of</strong><br />

many different traditions in recent years. For an overview <strong>and</strong> a general definition, see my<br />

article "Intentionality" (co-authored with John Haugel<strong>and</strong>) in Gregory 1987. For more<br />

detailed analyses, see my earlier books ( 1969, 1978, 1987b).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!