21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

466 ON THE ORIGIN OF MORALITY<br />

tion for <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> defense <strong>and</strong> reaction, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> successful<br />

counteractions. [Second Essay, sec. 12, pp. 77-78. f<br />

Considering that Nietzsche may never have read <strong>Darwin's</strong> own work, his<br />

appreciation <strong>of</strong> its major directions is remarkable, but he ra<strong>the</strong>r spoiled his<br />

record as a sound Darwinian by lapsing, on <strong>the</strong> same page, into skyhook<br />

hunger, announcing his "fundamental opposition to <strong>the</strong> now prevalent instinct<br />

<strong>and</strong> taste which would ra<strong>the</strong>r be reconciled even to <strong>the</strong> absolute<br />

fortuitousness, even <strong>the</strong> mechanistic senselessness <strong>of</strong> all events than to <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ory that in all events a will to power is operating." Nietzsche's idea <strong>of</strong> a<br />

will to power is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> stranger incarnations <strong>of</strong> skyhook hunger, <strong>and</strong>,<br />

fortunately, few find it attractive today. But, if we set that aside, <strong>the</strong> upshot<br />

<strong>of</strong> Nietzsche's genealogy <strong>of</strong> morals is that we must be extremely careful not<br />

to read into <strong>the</strong> history we extrapolate from nature any simplistic conclusions<br />

about value:<br />

The question: what is <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> this or that table <strong>of</strong> values <strong>and</strong> "morals"?<br />

should be viewed from <strong>the</strong> most divers perspectives; for <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

"value for what?" cannot be examined too subtly. Something, for example,<br />

that possessed obvious value in relation to <strong>the</strong> longest possible survival <strong>of</strong><br />

a race (or to <strong>the</strong> enhancement <strong>of</strong> its power <strong>of</strong> adaptation to a particular<br />

climate or to <strong>the</strong> preservation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> greatest number) would by no means<br />

possess <strong>the</strong> same value if it were a question, for instance, <strong>of</strong> producing a<br />

stronger type. The well-being <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> well-being <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> few<br />

are opposite viewpoints <strong>of</strong> value: to consider <strong>the</strong> former a priori <strong>of</strong> higher<br />

value may be left to <strong>the</strong> naivete <strong>of</strong> English biologists. [Nietzsche 1887, First<br />

Essay, sec. 17.]<br />

It is Spencer, clearly, not Darwin, whom Nietzsche is accusing <strong>of</strong> naivete<br />

about value. Both Spencer <strong>and</strong> Ree thought <strong>the</strong>y could see a straight, simple<br />

path to altruism (Hoy 1986, p. 29). We can see Nietzsche's criticism <strong>of</strong> this<br />

Panglossianism as a clear forerunner <strong>of</strong> George Williams' criticism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Panglossianism <strong>of</strong> naive group selectionism (see chapter 11). Spencer, in our<br />

terms, was an egregiously greedy reductionist, trying to derive "ought" from<br />

"is" in a single step. But doesn't this reveal <strong>the</strong> deeper problem with all<br />

sociobiology? Haven't <strong>the</strong> philosophers shown us that you can never derive<br />

"ought" from "is," no matter how many steps you take? Some have<br />

4. It is interesting to note that Nietzsche also had a thoroughly sound <strong>and</strong> modern idea<br />

about <strong>the</strong> relationship between complexity <strong>and</strong> any notion <strong>of</strong> global progress: "The<br />

richest <strong>and</strong> most complex forms—for <strong>the</strong> expression 'higher type' means no more than<br />

this—perish more easily: only <strong>the</strong> lowest preserve an apparent indestructibility"<br />

(Nietzsche 1901, p. 684).<br />

Sotne Varieties <strong>of</strong> Greedy Ethical Reductionism 467<br />

argued that sociobiology, no matter how sophisticated it became, no matter<br />

how many cranes it employed, could never bridge <strong>the</strong> gap between <strong>the</strong> "is"<br />

<strong>of</strong> empirical scientific fact <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> "ought" <strong>of</strong> ethics! (They say this with<br />

impressive passion.) That is <strong>the</strong> conviction we must examine next.<br />

3. SOME VARIETIES OF GREEDY ETHICAL REDUCTIONISM<br />

One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shibboleths <strong>of</strong> contemporary philosophy is that you can't derive<br />

"ought" from "is." Attempting to do this is <strong>of</strong>ten called <strong>the</strong> naturalistic<br />

fallacy, taking <strong>the</strong> term from G. E. Moore's classic, Principia Ethica ( 1903 ).<br />

As <strong>the</strong> philosopher Bernard Williams points out (1983, p. 556 ), <strong>the</strong>re really<br />

are several issues here. Naturalism "consists in <strong>the</strong> attempt to lay down<br />

certain fundamental aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good life for man on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> considerations<br />

<strong>of</strong> human nature." Naturalism wouldn't be refuted by <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

obvious fact that you can't derive any simple "ought" statement from any<br />

simple "is" statement. Consider: does it follow logically that I ought to give<br />

you five dollars from <strong>the</strong> fact ( <strong>and</strong> suppose it is a fact) that I said I would<br />

give you five dollars? Obviously not; any number <strong>of</strong> intervening excusing<br />

conditions might be cited to block this inference. Even if we were to characterize<br />

my saying as promising—an ethically loaded description—no simple<br />

"ought" statement follows directly.<br />

But reflections like this make scarcely a dent on naturalism as a <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

goal. Philosophers distinguish between finding <strong>the</strong> necessary <strong>and</strong> sufficient<br />

conditions for various things, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> distinction in this<br />

case actually helps clarify <strong>the</strong> situation. It is one thing to deny that<br />

collections <strong>of</strong> facts about <strong>the</strong> natural world are necessary to ground an<br />

ethical conclusion, <strong>and</strong> quite ano<strong>the</strong>r to deny that any collection <strong>of</strong> such facts<br />

is sufficient. According to st<strong>and</strong>ard doctrine, if we stay firmly planted in <strong>the</strong><br />

realm <strong>of</strong> facts about <strong>the</strong> world as it is, we will never find any collection <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>m, taken as axioms, from which any particular ethical conclusion can be<br />

conclusively proven. You can't get <strong>the</strong>re from here, any more than you can<br />

get from any consistent set <strong>of</strong> axioms about arithmetic to all <strong>the</strong> true<br />

statements <strong>of</strong> arithmetic.<br />

Well, so what? We may bring out <strong>the</strong> force <strong>of</strong> this rhetorical question with<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r one, ra<strong>the</strong>r more pointed: If "ought" cannot be derived from "is,"<br />

just what can "ought" be derived from? Is ethics an entirely "autonomous"<br />

field <strong>of</strong> inquiry? Does it float, unte<strong>the</strong>red to facts from any o<strong>the</strong>r discipline<br />

or tradition? Do our moral intuitions arise from some inexplicable ethics<br />

module implanted in our brains (or our "hearts," to speak with tradition)?<br />

that would be a dubious skyhook on which to hang our deepest convictions<br />

about what is right <strong>and</strong> wrong. Colin McGinn notes:<br />

A

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!