21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

456 ON THE ORIGIN OF MORALITY<br />

transfer, language. In Rawls' thought experiment about how a society ought<br />

to be formed, we are to imagine a time, at <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> society, when its<br />

inhabitants ga<strong>the</strong>r to consider what sort <strong>of</strong> design <strong>the</strong>ir society shall have.<br />

They are to reason toge<strong>the</strong>r about this until <strong>the</strong>y achieve what Rawls calls<br />

"reflective equilibrium"—a stable agreement that cannot be upset by fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

consideration. In this regard, Rawls' idea is like Maynard Smith's idea <strong>of</strong> an<br />

evolutionarily stable strategy or ESS, but with a major difference: <strong>the</strong>se are<br />

people doing die calculation, not birds or pine trees or o<strong>the</strong>r simple<br />

competitors in <strong>the</strong> games <strong>of</strong> life. The key innovation in Rawls' scenario, designed<br />

to ensure that undue selfishness among <strong>the</strong> participants in this exercise<br />

in reflection cancels itself out, is what he calls <strong>the</strong> "veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance."<br />

Everyone gets to vote on a favored design <strong>of</strong> society, but when you decide<br />

which society you would be happy to live in <strong>and</strong> give your allegiance to, you<br />

vote without knowing what your particular role or niche in it will be. You<br />

may be a senator or a surgeon or a street-sweeper or a soldier; you don't get<br />

to find out until after you have voted. Choosing from behind <strong>the</strong> veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance<br />

ensures that people will give due consideration to <strong>the</strong> likely effects,<br />

<strong>the</strong> costs <strong>and</strong> benefits, for all <strong>the</strong> citizenry, including those worst <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Rawls' <strong>the</strong>ory has received, <strong>and</strong> deserved, more attention than any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

work in ethics in this century, <strong>and</strong>, as usual, I am presenting an oversimplified<br />

version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issues. My point is to draw attention to <strong>the</strong> placement <strong>of</strong><br />

this work, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> work that it has provoked <strong>and</strong> inspired, relative to<br />

Darwinian thinking in general, <strong>and</strong> "evolutionary ethics" in particular. Note<br />

especially that, whereas Hobbes presented a rational reconstruction <strong>of</strong><br />

something that actually happened—something that must have happened—<br />

Rawls presents a thought experiment about what, if it did happen, would be<br />

right. Rawls' project is not speculative history or prehistory, but an entirely<br />

normative project: an attempt to demonstrate how ethical questions ought to<br />

be answered, <strong>and</strong>, more particularly, an attempt to justify a set <strong>of</strong> ethical<br />

norms. Hobbes hoped to solve <strong>the</strong> normative problem about what ethics<br />

ought to be—Rawls' problem—but, greedy reductionist that he was, he tried<br />

to kill two birds with one stone: he also wanted to explain how such a thing<br />

as right <strong>and</strong> wrong came into existence in <strong>the</strong> first place, an exercise <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination in <strong>the</strong> Darwinian mode. Needless to say, life is more complicated<br />

than that, but it was a nice try.<br />

Hobbes' account in <strong>the</strong> Leviathan has a fine Panglossian ring to it—in both<br />

exapted senses <strong>of</strong> that popular word. First, by presupposing <strong>the</strong> rationality (or<br />

Prudence, as he called it) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> agents whose mutual solution society is<br />

supposed to be, he viewed <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> society as dictated by reason, a forced<br />

move, or at least strongly endorsed by reason, a Good Trick. In o<strong>the</strong>r words,<br />

Hobbes' tale is an adaptationist Just So Story—<strong>and</strong> none <strong>the</strong> worse for it.<br />

But, second, by appealing as it does to our sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good <strong>of</strong> our own<br />

species, it is apt to lull us into overly sanguine models <strong>of</strong> how it must have<br />

come about—<strong>and</strong> this is a serious criticism. It may occur to us<br />

E Pluribus Unum? 457<br />

that, however it came about, <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> morality was a good thing for us,<br />

but we should try not to indulge in that sort <strong>of</strong> reflection. No matter how true<br />

it may be, it cannot explain how <strong>the</strong>se practices, for which we are<br />

retrospectively so grateful, came into existence <strong>and</strong> persisted. Group rationality<br />

may not be assumed, any more than we may assume that since we<br />

have benefited mightily from <strong>the</strong> eukaryotic revolution, it is <strong>the</strong>reby explained.<br />

Group rationality, or cooperation, has to be achieved, <strong>and</strong> that is a<br />

major design task, whe<strong>the</strong>r we are considering alliances <strong>of</strong> prokaryotes or<br />

alliances <strong>of</strong> our more recent ancestors. In fact, much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> best work in<br />

ethics in recent years has concerned precisely this issue (e.g., Parfit 1984,<br />

Gauthier 1986, Gibbard 1985).<br />

Before looking more closely at <strong>the</strong> human predicament in this regard, we<br />

might consider more cautiously <strong>the</strong> metaphor that Hobbes invites us to take<br />

seriously, helping ourselves to <strong>the</strong> improved perspective provided by <strong>the</strong><br />

Darwinian Revolution that has intervened. In what regards is a society like a<br />

giant organism, <strong>and</strong> in what regards is it different?<br />

Multicellular organisms have solved <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> group solidarity. One<br />

never hears tales <strong>of</strong> a person's thumbs rising up in civil war against <strong>the</strong><br />

neighboring fingers, or <strong>of</strong> an eagle's wings going on strike, refusing to work<br />

unless some concession can be wrung from <strong>the</strong> beak or (more to <strong>the</strong> point)<br />

<strong>the</strong> gonads. And now that we have <strong>the</strong> genes-eye perspective from which to<br />

look at <strong>the</strong> world, this can strike us as something <strong>of</strong> a puzzle. Why don't<br />

<strong>the</strong>se rebellions happen? Each cell in a multicellular organism has its own<br />

strings <strong>of</strong> DNA, a complete set <strong>of</strong> genes for making a whole organism, <strong>and</strong> if<br />

genes are selfish, why do <strong>the</strong> genes in <strong>the</strong> thumb cells or wing cells so<br />

docilely cooperate with <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genes? Don't <strong>the</strong> DNA copies in <strong>the</strong><br />

thumbs <strong>and</strong> wings count as genes? (Are <strong>the</strong>y denied <strong>the</strong> vote? Why do <strong>the</strong>y<br />

put up with it?) As <strong>the</strong> biologist David Sloan Wilson <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosopher <strong>of</strong><br />

biology Elliot Sober (Wilson <strong>and</strong> Sober 1994) have suggested, we can learn<br />

a lot about our social problems <strong>of</strong> defection (e.g., promising <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n<br />

reneging on <strong>the</strong> promise) <strong>and</strong> Hardin's tragedy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> commons (see chapter<br />

9) by considering how our ancestors, going back to <strong>the</strong> first eukaryotes,<br />

managed to achieve "harmony <strong>and</strong> coordination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir parts." The lessons<br />

to be learned are tricky, however, because <strong>the</strong> cells that compose us belong<br />

to two very different categories.<br />

An average human is normally host to billions <strong>of</strong> symbiotic organisms<br />

belonging to perhaps a thous<strong>and</strong> different species.... His phenotype is not<br />

determined by his human genes alone but also by <strong>the</strong> genes <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong><br />

symbionts he happens to be infected with. The symbiont species an individual<br />

carries usually have a very varied provenance, with only a few being<br />

likely to have come from his parents. [Delius 1991, p. 85.]<br />

Am I an organism, or a community, or both? I am both—<strong>and</strong> more—but<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is a tremendous difference between <strong>the</strong> cells that are <strong>of</strong>ficially part <strong>of</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!