21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

400 LOSING OUR MINDS TO DARWIN<br />

Searle ends up denying William Paley's premise: according to Searle, nature<br />

does not consist <strong>of</strong> an unimaginable variety <strong>of</strong> functioning devices, exhibiting<br />

design. Only human artifacts have that honor, <strong>and</strong> only because (as Locke<br />

"showed" us) it takes a Mind to make something with a function! 14 Searle<br />

insists that human minds have "Original" Intentionality, a property<br />

unattainable in principle by any R-<strong>and</strong>-D process <strong>of</strong> building better <strong>and</strong> better<br />

algorithms. This is a pure expression <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> belief in skyhooks: minds are<br />

original <strong>and</strong> inexplicable sources <strong>of</strong> design, not results <strong>of</strong> design. He defends<br />

this position more vividly than o<strong>the</strong>r philosophers, but he is not alone. The<br />

hostility to Artificial Intelligence <strong>and</strong> its evil twin, Darwinism, lies just<br />

beneath <strong>the</strong> surface <strong>of</strong> much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most influential work in recent twentiethcentury<br />

philosophy, as we shall see in <strong>the</strong> next chapter.<br />

CHAPTER FOURTEEN<br />

The <strong>Evolution</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Meaning</strong>s<br />

CHAPTER 13: When generate-<strong>and</strong>-test, <strong>the</strong> basic move in any Darwinian<br />

algorithm, moves into <strong>the</strong> brains <strong>of</strong> individual organisms, it builds a series <strong>of</strong><br />

ever more powerful systems, culminating in <strong>the</strong> defiberate, foresightful generation<br />

<strong>and</strong> testing <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories by human beings. This process<br />

creates minds that show no signs <strong>of</strong> "cognitive closure," thanks to <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

capacity to generate <strong>and</strong> comprehend language. Noam Chomsky, who created<br />

contemporary linguistics by proving that language was generated by an<br />

innate automaton, has never<strong>the</strong>less resisted all evolutionary accounts <strong>of</strong> how<br />

<strong>and</strong> why <strong>the</strong> language automaton got designed <strong>and</strong> installed, <strong>and</strong> has also<br />

resisted all Artificial Intelligence attempts to model language use. Chomsky<br />

has stood firm against (reverse) engineering, flanked by Gould on one side<br />

<strong>and</strong> Searle on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, exemplifying <strong>the</strong> resistance to <strong>the</strong> spread <strong>of</strong> <strong>Darwin's</strong><br />

dangerous idea, <strong>and</strong> holding out for <strong>the</strong> human mind as a skyhook.<br />

CHAPTER 14: In chapter 8, 1 sketched an evolutionary account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong><br />

meaning, which will now be exp<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> defended against <strong>the</strong> skeptical<br />

challenges <strong>of</strong> philosophers. A series <strong>of</strong> thought experiments building on <strong>the</strong><br />

concepts introduced in earlier chapters shows not just <strong>the</strong> coherence but <strong>the</strong><br />

inevitability <strong>of</strong> an evolutionary <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> meaning.<br />

14. Given Searle's position on this, one would predict that he should be utterly opposed<br />

to my analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> adaptationist thinking, as presented in chapter 9. He is. I<br />

don't know whe<strong>the</strong>r he has expressed this view in print, but in several debates with me<br />

(Rutgers, 1986; Buenos Aires, 1989), he has expressed <strong>the</strong> view that my account is<br />

exactly backward: <strong>the</strong> idea that one can hunt for <strong>the</strong> "free-floating rationales" <strong>of</strong> evolutionary<br />

selection processes is, in his view, a travesty <strong>of</strong> Darwinian thinking. One <strong>of</strong> us has<br />

unintentionally refuted himself; <strong>the</strong> identity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> victim is left as an exercise for <strong>the</strong><br />

reader.<br />

1. THE QUEST FOR REAL MEANING<br />

"When I use a word," Humpty Dumpty said, in a radier scornful tone,<br />

"it means just what I choose it to mean—nei<strong>the</strong>r more nor less."<br />

"The question is," said Alice, "whe<strong>the</strong>r you can make words mean so<br />

many different tilings."<br />

"The question is," said Humpty Dumpty, "which is to be master—<br />

that's all."<br />

—LEWIS CARROLL 1871<br />

There is no topic in philosophy that has received more attention than<br />

meaning, in its multifarious manifestations. At <strong>the</strong> gr<strong>and</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spectrum,<br />

philosophers <strong>of</strong> all schools have grappled with <strong>the</strong> ultimate question <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> life (<strong>and</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r or not this question has any meaning). At<br />

<strong>the</strong> modest end, philosophers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contemporary analytic school—<br />

sometimes called "linguistic philosophy" by outsiders—have subjected <strong>the</strong><br />

nuances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> words <strong>and</strong> whole utterances to microscopic<br />

scrutiny, in a variety <strong>of</strong> quite distinct enterprises. Back in <strong>the</strong> 1950s <strong>and</strong><br />

1960s, <strong>the</strong> school <strong>of</strong> "ordinary language philosophy" lavished attention on<br />

<strong>the</strong> subtle differences between particular words—<strong>the</strong> differences between<br />

doing something "deliberately" or "intentionally" or "on purpose," to cite a<br />

famous instance (Austin 1961). This gave way to a more formal <strong>and</strong> systematic<br />

set <strong>of</strong> investigations. Which different propositions could you mean<br />

by uttering such sentences as<br />

Tom believes that Ortcutt is a spy.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!