21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

486 ON THE ORIGIN OF MORALITY<br />

MIT: it was called Maze War, <strong>and</strong> more than one person could play it at once,<br />

each at a separate terminal linked to a central time-sharing computer. On <strong>the</strong><br />

screen you saw a simple perspective line drawing <strong>of</strong> a maze, in which you,<br />

<strong>the</strong> viewer, were situated. Corridors could be seen up ahead leading <strong>of</strong>f to left<br />

<strong>and</strong> right, <strong>and</strong> by pressing keys on <strong>the</strong> keyboard you could move forward <strong>and</strong><br />

back, or turn ninety degrees to <strong>the</strong> left or <strong>the</strong> right. Ano<strong>the</strong>r key on <strong>the</strong><br />

keyboard was <strong>the</strong> trigger <strong>of</strong> your gun, which fired straight ahead. All <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r players were in <strong>the</strong> same virtual maze, w<strong>and</strong>ering around, looking for<br />

someone to shoot, <strong>and</strong> hoping not to be shot. If one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r players<br />

crossed your path, he would show up as a simple cartoon figure, whom you<br />

would hope to shoot before it turned, saw you, <strong>and</strong> shot you. After a few<br />

minutes <strong>of</strong> frantic play, in which I was "shot" from behind several times, I<br />

found my mounting paranoia so uncomfortable that I sought relief: I found a<br />

cul-de-sac in <strong>the</strong> maze, backed myself into it, <strong>and</strong> just sat <strong>the</strong>re, relatively<br />

calmly, with my finger on <strong>the</strong> trigger. It struck me <strong>the</strong>n that I had adopted <strong>the</strong><br />

policy <strong>of</strong> a moray eel, patiently waiting in its well-protected hole for<br />

something strike-worthy to swim by.<br />

Now, does my behavior on this occasion give us any reason to suppose<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is a genetic predisposition to moray-eel behavior in Homo sapiens? Did<br />

<strong>the</strong> stress <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> occasion dredge up some ancient policy, lying dormant in<br />

my genes since <strong>the</strong> days when my ancestors were still fish? Of course not.<br />

The strategy is just too obvious. It felt like a forced move, but it was at least a<br />

Good Trick. We would not be surprised to find Martians backing <strong>the</strong>mselves<br />

self-protectively into Martian caves, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> likelihood that Martians had<br />

morays for ancestors would presumably not be adjusted upwards from zero<br />

by <strong>the</strong> discovery. It is true that I am distantly related to moray eels, but <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that I found this strategy in this environment is surely just a matter <strong>of</strong> its<br />

obvious excellence, given my needs <strong>and</strong> desires <strong>and</strong> my own assessment <strong>of</strong><br />

my limitations at <strong>the</strong> time. This illustrates <strong>the</strong> fundamental obstacle—not<br />

insuperable, but much larger than is commonly acknowledged—to inference<br />

in human sociobiology: showing that a particular type <strong>of</strong> human behavior is<br />

ubiquitous or nearly ubiquitous in widely separated human cultures goes no<br />

way at all towards showing that <strong>the</strong>re is a genetic predisposition for that<br />

particular behavior. So far as I know, in every culture known to<br />

anthropologists, <strong>the</strong> hunters throw <strong>the</strong>ir spears pointy-end-first, but this<br />

obviously doesn't establish that <strong>the</strong>re is a pointy-end-first gene that<br />

approaches fixation in our species.<br />

Nonhuman species can exhibit a similar, if reduced, capacity to reinvent<br />

<strong>the</strong> wheel, even though <strong>the</strong>y lack culture. Octopuses are remarkably intelligent,<br />

<strong>and</strong> although <strong>the</strong>y show no signs <strong>of</strong> cultural transmission, <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

smart enough so that we should not be surprised to discover <strong>the</strong>m individually<br />

hitting upon lots <strong>of</strong> Good Tricks that had never been posed as specific<br />

problems to <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors. Any such uniformity might be misread by<br />

Sociobiology: Good <strong>and</strong> Bad, Good <strong>and</strong> Evil 487<br />

biologists as signs <strong>of</strong> a special "instinct," when in fact it was just <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

general intelligence that led <strong>the</strong>m again <strong>and</strong> again to hit upon <strong>the</strong> same bright<br />

idea. The problem <strong>of</strong> interpretation for Homo sapiens is multiplied many<br />

times over by <strong>the</strong> fact <strong>of</strong> cultural transmission. Even if some individual<br />

hunters are not bright enough to figure out for <strong>the</strong>mselves that <strong>the</strong>y should<br />

throw <strong>the</strong> pointy end first, <strong>the</strong>y will be told to do so by <strong>the</strong>ir peers, or will<br />

just notice <strong>the</strong>ir practice, <strong>and</strong> will appreciate <strong>the</strong> results immediately. In o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

words, if you are not totally idiotic, you don't need a genetic basis for any<br />

adaptation that you will pick up from your friends in any case.<br />

It is hard to believe that sociobiologists can make <strong>the</strong> mistake <strong>of</strong> ignoring<br />

this omnipresent possibility, but <strong>the</strong> evidence is striking that <strong>the</strong>y have done<br />

so, again <strong>and</strong> again ( Kitcher 1985 )• Many instances could be listed, but I will<br />

concentrate on a particularly visible <strong>and</strong> well-known case. Although E. O.<br />

Wilson (1978, p. 35) states clearly that <strong>the</strong> human behaviors to be accounted<br />

for by specific genetic hypo<strong>the</strong>ses should be <strong>the</strong> "least rational <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human<br />

repertoire— In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong>y should implicate innate, biological<br />

phenomena that are <strong>the</strong> least susceptible to mimicry by culture," he goes on<br />

(pp. 107ff.) to claim, for instance, that <strong>the</strong> evidence <strong>of</strong> territoriality in all<br />

human cultures (we human beings like to call a bit <strong>of</strong> space our own) is clear<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> that we, like very many o<strong>the</strong>r species, have a genetic predisposition<br />

wired in at birth for <strong>the</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> territory. That may be true—in fact, it<br />

would not be at all surprising, since many species manifestly do exhibit innate<br />

territoriality, <strong>and</strong> it is hard to think <strong>of</strong> what force <strong>the</strong>re might be to remove<br />

such a disposition from our genetic makeup. But <strong>the</strong> ubiquity <strong>of</strong> territoriality<br />

in human societies is by itself no evidence at all for this, since territoriality<br />

makes so much sense in so many human arrangements. It is, if not a forced<br />

move, close to it.<br />

The very considerations that in o<strong>the</strong>r parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> biosphere count for an<br />

explanation in terms <strong>of</strong> natural selection <strong>of</strong> an adaptation—manifest utility,<br />

obvious value, undeniable reasonableness <strong>of</strong> design—count against <strong>the</strong> need<br />

for any such explanation in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> human behavior. If a trick is that good,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n it will be routinely rediscovered by every culture, without need <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

genetic descent or cultural transmission <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particulars. 11 We saw in<br />

chapter 12 that it is <strong>the</strong> prospect <strong>of</strong> convergent cultural evolution—<br />

reinventing <strong>the</strong> wheel—that plays havoc with our attempts to turn memet-ics<br />

into a science. The same difficulty besets all attempts to infer genetic<br />

11. A useful exercise when considering any such case is to imagine creating a roomful <strong>of</strong><br />

roughly rational robots ( smart, but with no genetic ancestry at all) <strong>and</strong> asking yourself if<br />

<strong>the</strong>y would soon settle into <strong>the</strong> behavior in question. (If <strong>the</strong> case is complex, a computer<br />

simulation should be used, as a pros<strong>the</strong>tic guide to your imagination.) If so, it is not so<br />

surprising that human beings everywhere do it, too, <strong>and</strong> it probably has nothing to do<br />

with <strong>the</strong>ir primate heritage, <strong>the</strong>ir mammalian heritage, even <strong>the</strong>ir vertebrate heritage.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!