21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

462 ON THE ORIGIN OF MORALITY<br />

<strong>the</strong> weak, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Social Darwinist nonsense. It is amusing to note<br />

that <strong>the</strong> fundamental (bad) argument <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Social Darwinists is identical to a<br />

(bad) argument used by many religious fundamentalists. Whereas <strong>the</strong><br />

fundamentalists sometimes begin <strong>the</strong>ir arguments by saying, "If God had<br />

intended Man to ... [fly, wear clo<strong>the</strong>s, drink alcohol,...]," <strong>the</strong> Social Darwinists<br />

begin <strong>the</strong>irs by saying, in effect, "If Mo<strong>the</strong>r Nature had intended Man<br />

to...," <strong>and</strong> even though Mo<strong>the</strong>r Nature (natural selection) can be viewed as<br />

having intentions, in <strong>the</strong> limited sense <strong>of</strong> having retrospectively endorsed<br />

features for one reason or ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>se earlier endorsements may count for<br />

nothing now, since circumstances have changed.<br />

Among <strong>the</strong> Social Darwinists' ideas was a political agenda: efforts by dogooders<br />

to provide nurture for <strong>the</strong> least fortunate members <strong>of</strong> society are<br />

counterproductive; such efforts permit those to replicate whom nature would<br />

wisely cull. These are abominable ideas, but <strong>the</strong>y were not <strong>the</strong> primary target<br />

<strong>of</strong> Nietzsche's criticism. His primary target was <strong>the</strong> historical naivete <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Social Darwinists (Hoy 1986), <strong>the</strong>ir Panglossian optimism about <strong>the</strong> ready<br />

adaptability <strong>of</strong> human reason (or Prudence) to Morality. Nietzsche saw <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

complacency as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir heritage as "English psychologists"—<br />

intellectual descendants <strong>of</strong> Hume. He noted <strong>the</strong>ir desire to avoid skyhooks:<br />

These English psychologists—what do <strong>the</strong>y really want? One always discovers<br />

<strong>the</strong>m ... seeking <strong>the</strong> truly effective <strong>and</strong> directing agent, that which<br />

has been decisive in its evolution, in just that place where <strong>the</strong> intellectual<br />

pride <strong>of</strong> man would least desire to find it (in <strong>the</strong> vis inertiae <strong>of</strong> habit, for<br />

example, or in forgetfulness, or in a blind <strong>and</strong> chance mechanistic hookingtoge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>of</strong> ideas, or in something purely passive, automatic, reflexive,<br />

molecular, <strong>and</strong> thoroughly stupid)—what is it really that always drives<br />

<strong>the</strong>se psychologists in just this direction? Is it a secret, malicious, vulgar,<br />

perhaps self-deceiving instinct for belittling man? [Nietzsche 1887, First<br />

Essay, sec. 1, p. 24.]<br />

Nietzsche's antidote to <strong>the</strong> banalities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> "English psychologists" was a<br />

very "continental" romanticism. They thought <strong>the</strong> passage from <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong><br />

nature to morality was easy, or at least quite presentable, but that was<br />

because <strong>the</strong>y just made up <strong>the</strong>ir stories <strong>and</strong> didn't bo<strong>the</strong>r looking at <strong>the</strong> clues<br />

<strong>of</strong> history, which told a darker tale.<br />

Nietzsche began, as Hobbes had done, by imagining a premoral world <strong>of</strong><br />

human life, but he divided his story <strong>of</strong> transition into two phases (<strong>and</strong> told<br />

his tales in reverse order, starting in <strong>the</strong> middle, something that confuses<br />

many readers). Hobbes had noted (1651, pt. I, ch. 14) that <strong>the</strong> very existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> any practice <strong>of</strong> forming contracts or compacts depends on <strong>the</strong> capacity <strong>of</strong><br />

human beings to make promises about <strong>the</strong> future, <strong>and</strong> what<br />

Friedrich Nietzsche's Just So Stories 463<br />

struck Nietzsche was that this capacity does not come for free. This was <strong>the</strong><br />

topic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Second Essay <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> three that make up <strong>the</strong> Genealogy-. "To<br />

breed an animal with <strong>the</strong> right to make promises—is not this <strong>the</strong> paradoxical<br />

task that nature has set itself in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> man? is it not <strong>the</strong> real problem<br />

regarding man?" (Second Essay, sec. 1, p. 57). This "long story <strong>of</strong> how<br />

responsibility originated" is a story <strong>of</strong> how early human beings learned to<br />

torture each o<strong>the</strong>r—literally—into developing a special kind <strong>of</strong> memory, <strong>the</strong><br />

memory needed to keep track <strong>of</strong> debts <strong>and</strong> credits. "Buying <strong>and</strong> selling,<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong>ir psychological appurtenances, are older even than <strong>the</strong><br />

beginnings <strong>of</strong> any kind <strong>of</strong> social forms <strong>of</strong> organization <strong>and</strong> alliances" (Second<br />

Essay, sec. 8, p. 70). The capacity to detect cheating, to remember <strong>the</strong><br />

promise broken <strong>and</strong> punish <strong>the</strong> cheater, had to be drilled into our ancestors'<br />

brains, Nietzsche surmised: "Its beginnings were, like <strong>the</strong> beginnings <strong>of</strong><br />

everything great on earth, soaked in blood thoroughly <strong>and</strong> for a long time"<br />

(Second Essay, sec. 6, p. 65 ). What is Nietzsche's evidence for all this? An<br />

imaginative—not to say unbridled—reading <strong>of</strong> what we might call <strong>the</strong> fossil<br />

record <strong>of</strong> human culture, in <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> ancient myths, surviving religious<br />

practices, archeological clues, <strong>and</strong> so forth. Leaving <strong>the</strong> gory details aside,<br />

fascinating though <strong>the</strong>y are, Nietzsche's suggestion is that eventually—perhaps<br />

via an instance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Baldwin Effect!—our ancestors "bred" an animal<br />

with an innate capacity to keep a promise, <strong>and</strong> a concomitant talent for<br />

detecting <strong>and</strong> punishing a promise-breaker.<br />

This permitted <strong>the</strong> formation <strong>of</strong> early societies, according to Nietzsche, but<br />

<strong>the</strong>re was still no morality—not in <strong>the</strong> sense that we recognize <strong>and</strong> honor<br />

today. The second transition occurred in historical times, he claimed, <strong>and</strong> can<br />

be traced via etymological reconstruction <strong>and</strong> a proper reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> texts <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> last two millennia—an adaptation by Nietzsche <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> philological<br />

methods that he had been trained to use. To read <strong>the</strong>se clues in a new way,<br />

you need a <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>and</strong> Nietzsche had one, developed in opposition<br />

to <strong>the</strong> tacit <strong>the</strong>ory he discerned in <strong>the</strong> Social Darwinists. The proto-citizens <strong>of</strong><br />

Nietzsche's second Just So Story (told in <strong>the</strong> First Essay) live in societies <strong>of</strong><br />

sorts, not Hobbes' state <strong>of</strong> nature, but <strong>the</strong> life he describes in <strong>the</strong>m is about<br />

equally nasty <strong>and</strong> brutish. Might made right—or, ra<strong>the</strong>r, might ruled. The<br />

people had concepts <strong>of</strong> good <strong>and</strong> bad, but not good <strong>and</strong> evil, right <strong>and</strong> wrong.<br />

Like Hobbes, Nietzsche tried to tell <strong>the</strong> tale <strong>of</strong> how <strong>the</strong>se latter memes arose.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most daring (<strong>and</strong> ultimately least persuasive ) <strong>of</strong> his speculations<br />

is that <strong>the</strong> memes for ( moral) good <strong>and</strong> evil Were not just minor<br />

permutations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir amoral predecessors; <strong>the</strong> memes traded places. What<br />

had been good ( old-style ) became evil ( new-style ), <strong>and</strong> what had been bad<br />

(old-style) became (morally) good (new-style). This "transvaluation <strong>of</strong><br />

values" was, for Nietzsche, <strong>the</strong> key event in <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> ethics, <strong>and</strong> he<br />

explicitly opposed it to Herbert Spencer's bl<strong>and</strong> supposition that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!