21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

100 THE TREE OF LIFE<br />

which it followed that <strong>the</strong>y were—as <strong>the</strong>y later turn out to be—<strong>the</strong> founders<br />

<strong>of</strong> a new species. We can imagine, if we want, an extreme (<strong>and</strong> improbable)<br />

case in which a single mutation guarantees reproductive isolation in a single<br />

generation, but, <strong>of</strong> course, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> individual who has that<br />

mutation counts as a species-founder or simply as a freak <strong>of</strong> nature depends<br />

on nothing in its individual makeup or biography, but on what happens to<br />

subsequent generations—if any—<strong>of</strong> its <strong>of</strong>fspring.<br />

Darwin was not able to present a single instance <strong>of</strong> speciation by natural<br />

selection in Origin <strong>of</strong> Species. His strategy in that book was to develop in<br />

detail <strong>the</strong> evidence that artificial selection by dog- <strong>and</strong> pigeon-breeders could<br />

build up large differences by a series <strong>of</strong> gradual changes. He <strong>the</strong>n pointed out<br />

that deliberate choice by title animals' keepers was inessential; <strong>the</strong> runts <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> litter tended not to be valued, <strong>and</strong> hence tended not to reproduce as much<br />

as <strong>the</strong>ir more valued siblings, so, without any conscious policy <strong>of</strong> breeding,<br />

human animal-keepers presided unwittingly over a steady process <strong>of</strong> design<br />

revision. He <strong>of</strong>fered <strong>the</strong> nice example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> King Charles spaniel, "which<br />

has been unconsciously modified to a large extent since <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong> that<br />

monarch" (Origin, p. 35)—as can be confirmed by a careful examination <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> dogs in various portraits <strong>of</strong> King Charles. He called such cases<br />

"unconscious selection" by human domesticators, <strong>and</strong> he used it as a<br />

persuasive bridge to get his readers to <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>of</strong> even more<br />

unconscious selection by <strong>the</strong> impersonal environment. But he had to admit,<br />

when challenged, that he could provide no cases <strong>of</strong> animal-breeders'<br />

producing a new species. Such breeding had definitely produced different<br />

varieties, but not a single new species. Dachshund <strong>and</strong> St. Bernard were not<br />

different species, however different in appearance. Darwin admitted as much,<br />

but he might quite correctly have gone on to point out that it was simply too<br />

early to tell whe<strong>the</strong>r he had given any examples <strong>of</strong> speciation accomplished<br />

by artificial selection. Any lady's lapdog could at some future date be<br />

discovered to have been <strong>the</strong> founding member <strong>of</strong> a species that split <strong>of</strong>f from<br />

Canis familiaris.<br />

The same moral applies to <strong>the</strong> creation <strong>of</strong> new genera, families, <strong>and</strong> even<br />

kingdoms, <strong>of</strong> course. The major branching that we would retrospectively<br />

crown as <strong>the</strong> parting <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> plants from <strong>the</strong> animals began as a segregation <strong>of</strong><br />

two gene pools every bit as inscrutable <strong>and</strong> unremarkable at <strong>the</strong> time as any<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r temporary drifting apart <strong>of</strong> members <strong>of</strong> a single population.<br />

4. PATTERNS, OVERSIMPLIFICATION, AND EXPLANATION<br />

Much more interesting than <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> how to draw <strong>the</strong> species boundary<br />

are all <strong>the</strong> questions about <strong>the</strong> shapes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> branches—<strong>and</strong> even more<br />

interesting, <strong>the</strong> shapes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> empty spaces between <strong>the</strong> branches. What<br />

Patterns, Oversimplification, <strong>and</strong> Explanation 101<br />

trends, forces, principles—or historical events—have influenced <strong>the</strong>se<br />

shapes or made <strong>the</strong>m possible? Eyes have evolved independently in dozens<br />

<strong>of</strong> lineages, but fea<strong>the</strong>rs probably only once. As John Maynard Smith observes,<br />

mammals go in for horns but birds do not. "Why should <strong>the</strong> pattern<br />

<strong>of</strong> variation be limited in this way? The short answer is that we do not know"<br />

(Maynard Smith 1986, p. 41).<br />

We can't rewind <strong>the</strong> tope <strong>of</strong> life <strong>and</strong> replay it to see what happens next<br />

time, alas, so <strong>the</strong> only way to answer questions about such huge <strong>and</strong> experimentally<br />

inaccessible patterns is to leap boldly into <strong>the</strong> void with <strong>the</strong><br />

risky tactic <strong>of</strong> deliberate oversimplification. This tactic has a long <strong>and</strong> distinguished<br />

history in science, but it tends to provoke controversy, since<br />

scientists have different thresholds at which <strong>the</strong>y get nervous about playing<br />

fast <strong>and</strong> loose with <strong>the</strong> recalcitrant details. Newtonian physics was overthrown<br />

by Einstein, but it is still a good approximation for almost all purposes.<br />

No physicist objects when NASA uses Newtonian physics to calculate<br />

<strong>the</strong> forces at lift<strong>of</strong>f <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> orbital trajectory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> space shuttle, but, strictly<br />

speaking, this is a deliberate use <strong>of</strong> a false <strong>the</strong>ory in order to make calculation<br />

feasible. In <strong>the</strong> same spirit, physiologists studying, say, mechanisms for<br />

changing <strong>the</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> metabolism try in general to avoid <strong>the</strong> bizarre complexities<br />

<strong>of</strong> subatomic quantum physics, hoping that any quantum effects will<br />

cancel out or in o<strong>the</strong>r ways be beneath <strong>the</strong> threshold <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir models. In<br />

general, <strong>the</strong> tactic pays <strong>of</strong>f h<strong>and</strong>somely, but one can never be sure when one<br />

scientist's grubby complication will be elevated into ano<strong>the</strong>r scientist's Key to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Mystery. And it can just as well work <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around: <strong>the</strong> Key is<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten discovered by climbing out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> trenches <strong>and</strong> going for <strong>the</strong> panoramic<br />

view.<br />

I once got in a debate with Francis Crick about <strong>the</strong> virtues <strong>and</strong> vices <strong>of</strong><br />

Connectionism—<strong>the</strong> movement in cognitive science that models psychological<br />

phenomena by building up patterns in <strong>the</strong> connection-strengths<br />

between <strong>the</strong> nodes in very unrealistic <strong>and</strong> oversimplified "neural nets" simulated<br />

on computers. "These people may be good engineers," Crick averred<br />

(as best I recall), "but what <strong>the</strong>y are doing is terrible science! These people<br />

willfully turn <strong>the</strong>ir backs on what we already know about how neurons<br />

interact, so <strong>the</strong>ir models are utterly useless as models <strong>of</strong> brain function." This<br />

criticism somewhat surprised me, for Crick is famous for his own brilliant<br />

opportunism in uncovering <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> DNA; while o<strong>the</strong>rs struggled up<br />

<strong>the</strong> straight <strong>and</strong> narrow path <strong>of</strong> strict construction from <strong>the</strong> evidence, he <strong>and</strong><br />

Watson took a few daring <strong>and</strong> optimistic sidesteps, with gratifying results.<br />

But in any case, I was curious to know how widely he would cast his<br />

denunciation. Would he say <strong>the</strong> same thing about population geneticists? The<br />

derogatory term for some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir models is "bean-bag genetics," for <strong>the</strong>y<br />

pretend that genes for this <strong>and</strong> that are like so many color-coded beads on a<br />

string. What <strong>the</strong>y call a gene (or an allele at a locus)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!