21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

328 CONTROVERSIES CONTAINED Cut Bono? 329<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> principal beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir decisions, <strong>and</strong> many are afraid that<br />

Darwinism, in its gene-centered version, will undercut <strong>the</strong>ir assurance on that<br />

score. They are apt to see Dawkins' vivid picture <strong>of</strong> organisms as mere vehicles<br />

created to carry a gaggle <strong>of</strong> genes into future vehicles as intellectual assault <strong>and</strong><br />

battery. So one reason, I venture, why organism-level <strong>and</strong> group-level<br />

perspectives are so frequently hailed as a worthy opponent to <strong>the</strong> gene-level<br />

perspective is <strong>the</strong> background thought—never articulated— that we are<br />

organisms (<strong>and</strong> we live in groups that matter to us)—<strong>and</strong> we don't want our<br />

interests playing second fiddle to any o<strong>the</strong>rs! My hunch is, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, that<br />

we wouldn't care whe<strong>the</strong>r pine trees or hummingbirds were "mere survival<br />

machines" for <strong>the</strong>ir genes if it weren't for our realization that we bear <strong>the</strong> same<br />

relation to our genes that <strong>the</strong>y bear to <strong>the</strong>irs. In <strong>the</strong> next chapter, I want to put<br />

that worry to rest by showing that this is really not so! Our relationship to our<br />

genes is importantly different from <strong>the</strong> relationship <strong>of</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>r species to its<br />

genes—because what We are is not just what we as a species are. This will pull<br />

<strong>the</strong> plug, draining all <strong>the</strong> anxiety out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> still fascinating <strong>and</strong> unresolved<br />

conceptual questions about how to think about <strong>the</strong> units <strong>of</strong> selection, but before<br />

I turn to that task, I must make sure <strong>the</strong> threatening aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue is made<br />

clear, <strong>and</strong> several common misconceptions are cleared up.<br />

Perhaps <strong>the</strong> most misguided criticism <strong>of</strong> gene centrism is <strong>the</strong> frequently<br />

heard claim that genes simply cannot have interests (Midgley 1979, 1983,<br />

Stove 1992). This criticism, if taken seriously, would lead us to discard a<br />

treasury <strong>of</strong> insights, but it is flatly mistaken. Even if genes could not act on<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir interests in just <strong>the</strong> way we can act on ours, <strong>the</strong>y can surely have <strong>the</strong>m,<br />

in a sense that is uncontroversial <strong>and</strong> clear. If a body politic, or General<br />

Motors, can have interests, so can genes. You can do something for your own<br />

sake, or for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> children, or for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> art, or for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong><br />

democracy, or for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong>... peanut butter. I find it hard to imagine why<br />

anybody would want to put <strong>the</strong> well-being <strong>and</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r flourishing <strong>of</strong> peanut<br />

butter above all else, but peanut butter can be put on <strong>the</strong> pedestal just as<br />

readily as art or <strong>the</strong> children can. One could even decide—though it would be<br />

a strange choice—that <strong>the</strong> thing one wanted most to protect <strong>and</strong> enhance,<br />

even at <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> one's own life, was one's own genes. No sane person<br />

would make such a decision. As George Williams (1988, p. 403) says, "There<br />

is no conceivable justification for any personal concern with <strong>the</strong> interests<br />

(long-term average proliferation ) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genes we received in <strong>the</strong> lottery <strong>of</strong><br />

meiosis <strong>and</strong> fertilization."<br />

But that doesn't mean that <strong>the</strong>re aren't forces bent on fur<strong>the</strong>ring <strong>the</strong> sakes or<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> genes. In fact, until quite recently, genes were <strong>the</strong> principal<br />

beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> selective forces on <strong>the</strong> planet. That is to say, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

were no forces whose principal beneficiary was anything else. There were<br />

accidents <strong>and</strong> catastrophes (lightning bolts <strong>and</strong> tidal waves), but no steady<br />

forces acting systematically to favor anything but genes.<br />

To whose interests is <strong>the</strong> actual "decision-making" <strong>of</strong> natural selection<br />

most directly responsive? It is not controversial that conflicts between genes<br />

<strong>and</strong> bodies (between genes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenotypic expressions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genotypes<br />

<strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y are a proper part) can arise. Moreover, no one doubts that in<br />

general <strong>the</strong> body's claim to be considered <strong>the</strong> principal beneficiary lapses as<br />

soon as it has completed its procreational mission. Once <strong>the</strong> salmon have<br />

fought <strong>the</strong>ir way upstream <strong>and</strong> successfully spawned, <strong>the</strong>y are dead meat.<br />

They literally fall apart, because <strong>the</strong>re is no evolutionary pressure in favor <strong>of</strong><br />

any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> design revisions that might prevent <strong>the</strong>m from falling apart, giving<br />

<strong>the</strong>m nice long gr<strong>and</strong>parent-retirement periods like those many <strong>of</strong> us get to<br />

enjoy. In general, <strong>the</strong> body is thus only an instrumental, <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

secondary, beneficiary <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> "decisions" made by natural selection.<br />

This is true throughout <strong>the</strong> biosphere, revealed in a pattern with a few<br />

important variations. In many phyla, parents die before <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>of</strong>fspring are<br />

born, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir entire lives are a preparation for a single climactic act <strong>of</strong><br />

replication. O<strong>the</strong>rs—trees, for instance—live through many generations <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong>fspring, <strong>and</strong> can hence come into competition with <strong>the</strong>ir own young for<br />

sunlight <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r resources. Mammals <strong>and</strong> birds typically invest large portions<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir energy <strong>and</strong> activity to caring for young, <strong>and</strong> hence have many<br />

more opportunities to "choose" between <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir young as<br />

beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> whatever course <strong>of</strong> action <strong>the</strong>y take. Creatures for which<br />

such options never come up can be designed "under <strong>the</strong> assumption" (Mo<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Nature's tacit assumption) that this is simply not an issue that needs any<br />

design attention at all.<br />

Presumably, <strong>the</strong> control system <strong>of</strong> a moth, for instance, is ruthlessly designed<br />

to sacrifice <strong>the</strong> body for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genes, whenever a generic <strong>and</strong><br />

recognizable opportunity to do so arises. A little fantasy: We somehow<br />

surgically replace this st<strong>and</strong>ard system (a "Damn <strong>the</strong> torpedoes, full speed<br />

ahead!" system ) with a body-favoring system ( a "To hell with my genes, I'm<br />

looking out for Number One!" system). What could <strong>the</strong> replacement ever do<br />

that wasn't just one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> committing suicide or pointlessly<br />

w<strong>and</strong>ering? A moth is simply not equipped to take any advantage <strong>of</strong> opportunities<br />

tangential to its lifework <strong>of</strong> reproducing itself. <strong>Life</strong>-enhancing ends<br />

are hard to take seriously, if it is <strong>the</strong> short life <strong>of</strong> a moth we are considering.<br />

Birds, in contrast, may ab<strong>and</strong>on a nest full <strong>of</strong> eggs when <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves are<br />

threatened in one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> this looks more like what we <strong>of</strong>ten do,<br />

but <strong>the</strong> reason <strong>the</strong>y can do this is that <strong>the</strong>y can start ano<strong>the</strong>r nest—if not this<br />

season, <strong>the</strong>n next. They are looking out for Number One now, but only<br />

because this gives <strong>the</strong>ir genes a better chance <strong>of</strong> getting replicated later.<br />

We are different. There is a huge scope for alternative policies in human<br />

life, but <strong>the</strong> question <strong>the</strong>n becomes: how <strong>and</strong> when does this scope get<br />

established? There can be no doubt that many people have clearheadedly,<br />

well-informedly chosen to forgo <strong>the</strong> risks <strong>and</strong> pains <strong>of</strong> childbearing for <strong>the</strong><br />

safety <strong>and</strong> comfort <strong>of</strong> a "barren" life <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r rewards. The culture may stack

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!