21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

358 THE CRANES OF CULTURE Could There Be a Science <strong>of</strong> Memetics? 359<br />

a public representation, having formed a mental representation, <strong>and</strong> having<br />

followed it with greater or lesser success. What caused <strong>the</strong> child's enjoyable<br />

fear was not <strong>the</strong> story <strong>of</strong> Little Red Riding Hood in <strong>the</strong> abstract, but<br />

her underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> her mo<strong>the</strong>r's words. More to <strong>the</strong> present point, what<br />

caused <strong>the</strong> Mornay sauce recipe or <strong>the</strong> story <strong>of</strong> Little Red Riding Hood to<br />

become cultural representations is not, or ra<strong>the</strong>r is not directly, <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

formal properties, it is <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> mental representations<br />

causally linked by millions <strong>of</strong> public representations. [Sperber 1985,<br />

pp. 77-78.]<br />

What Sperber says about <strong>the</strong> indirectness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> abstract features is<br />

certainly true, but, far from this being an obstacle to science, it is <strong>the</strong> best sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> invitation to science: an invitation to cut through <strong>the</strong> Gordian knot <strong>of</strong><br />

tangled causation with an abstract formulation that is predictive precisely<br />

because it ignores all those complications. For instance, genes are selected<br />

because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir indirect <strong>and</strong> only statistically visible phenotypic effects.<br />

Consider <strong>the</strong> following prediction: wherever you find moths with camouflage<br />

on <strong>the</strong>ir wings, you will find that <strong>the</strong>y have keen-sighted predators, <strong>and</strong><br />

wherever you find moths that are heavily predated by echo-locating bats, you<br />

will find that <strong>the</strong>y have traded in wing camouflage for jamming devices or a<br />

particular talent for creating evasive flight patterns. Of course, our ultimate<br />

goal is to explain whatever features we find in <strong>the</strong> moths <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

surroundings all <strong>the</strong> way down to <strong>the</strong> molecular or atomic mechanisms<br />

responsible, but <strong>the</strong>re is no reason to dem<strong>and</strong> that such a reduction be<br />

uniform or generalizable across <strong>the</strong> board. It is <strong>the</strong> glory <strong>of</strong> science that it can<br />

find <strong>the</strong> patterns in spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> noise (Dennett 1991b).<br />

The peculiarities <strong>of</strong> human psychology (<strong>and</strong> human digestion, for that<br />

matter, as <strong>the</strong> Mornay-sauce example shows ) are important eventually, but<br />

<strong>the</strong>y don't st<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> way <strong>of</strong> a scientific analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon in<br />

question. In fact, as Sperber himself has persuasively argued, we can use<br />

higher-level principles as levers to pry open lower-level secrets. Sperber<br />

points to <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> invention <strong>of</strong> writing, which initiated major<br />

changes in cultural evolution. He shows how to reason from facts about<br />

preliterate culture to facts about human psychology. ( He prefers to think <strong>of</strong><br />

cultural transmission along <strong>the</strong> lines <strong>of</strong> epidemiology ra<strong>the</strong>r than genetics, but<br />

<strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> his <strong>the</strong>ory is very much <strong>the</strong> same as Dawkins'—to <strong>the</strong> point<br />

<strong>of</strong> near-indistinguishability when you think <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong> Darwinian treatment<br />

<strong>of</strong> epidemiology looks like; see Williams <strong>and</strong> Nesse 1991) Here is Sperber's<br />

"Law <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Epidemiology <strong>of</strong> Representations":<br />

In an oral tradition, all cultural representations are easily remembered<br />

ones; hard to remember representations are forgotten, or transformed into<br />

more easily remembered ones, before reaching a cultural level <strong>of</strong> distribution.<br />

[Sperber 1985, p. 86.]<br />

It looks trivial at first, but consider how we can apply it. We can use <strong>the</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> a particular sort <strong>of</strong> cultural representation endemic to oral<br />

traditions to shed light on how human memory works, by asking what it is<br />

about this sort <strong>of</strong> representation that makes it more memorable than o<strong>the</strong>rs.<br />

Sperber points out that people are better at remembering a story than <strong>the</strong>v<br />

are at remembering a text—at least today, now that <strong>the</strong> oral tradition is<br />

waning. 8 But even today we sometimes remember—involuntarily—an<br />

advertising jingle, including its precise rhythmic properties, its "tone <strong>of</strong><br />

voice," <strong>and</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>r "low-level" features. When scientists decide on<br />

acronyms or cute slogans for <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>the</strong>y are hoping <strong>the</strong>reby to make<br />

<strong>the</strong>m more memorable, more vivid <strong>and</strong> attractive memes. And hence <strong>the</strong><br />

actual details <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> representing are sometimes just as much a c<strong>and</strong>idate for<br />

memehood as <strong>the</strong> content represented. Using acronyms is itself a meme—a<br />

meta-meme, <strong>of</strong> course—which caught on because <strong>of</strong> its demonstrated power<br />

in fur<strong>the</strong>ring <strong>the</strong> content memes whose name memes it helped to design.<br />

What is it about acronyms, or about rhymes or "snappy" slogans, that makes<br />

<strong>the</strong>m fare so well in <strong>the</strong> competitions that rage through a human mind?<br />

This sort <strong>of</strong> question exploits a fundamental strategy both <strong>of</strong> evolutionary<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> cognitive science, as we have seen many times. Where evolutionary<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory considers information transmitted through genetic channels,<br />

whatever <strong>the</strong>y are, cognitive science considers information transmitted<br />

through <strong>the</strong> channels <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nervous system, whatever <strong>the</strong>y are—plus <strong>the</strong><br />

adjacent media, such as <strong>the</strong> translucent air, which transmits sound <strong>and</strong> light<br />

so well. You can finesse your ignorance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gory mechanical details <strong>of</strong><br />

how <strong>the</strong> information got from A to B, at least temporarily, <strong>and</strong> just concentrate<br />

on <strong>the</strong> implications <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that some information did get <strong>the</strong>re— <strong>and</strong><br />

some o<strong>the</strong>r information didn't.<br />

Suppose you were given <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> catching a spy, or a whole spy ring, in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Pentagon. Suppose what was known was that information about, say,<br />

nuclear submarines was somehow getting into <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wrong people.<br />

One way <strong>of</strong> catching <strong>the</strong> spy would be to insert various tidbits <strong>of</strong> false (but<br />

credible) information at various places within <strong>the</strong> Pentagon <strong>and</strong> see which<br />

ones surfaced, in which order, in Geneva or Beirut or wherever <strong>the</strong><br />

marketplace for secrets is. Varying <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>and</strong> circumstances, you<br />

might gradually build up an elaborate diagram <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> route—<strong>the</strong> various way<br />

stations <strong>and</strong> transfers <strong>and</strong> compounding places—even to <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong><br />

8. For an analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> astonishing mnemonic powers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> oral tradition, see Albert<br />

Lord's classic, The Singer <strong>of</strong> Tales (1960), about <strong>the</strong> technology <strong>of</strong> verse memorization<br />

developed by bards from Homer's day to modern times in <strong>the</strong> Balkan countries <strong>and</strong><br />

elsewhere.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!