21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

480 ON THE ORIGIN OF MORALITY<br />

The simple situations explored by Axelrod's initial tournament have given<br />

way to much more complex <strong>and</strong> realistic scenarios. Nowak <strong>and</strong> Sigmund<br />

(1993) have found a strategy that outperforms Tit for Tat under an important<br />

variety <strong>of</strong> circumstances. Kitcher (1993) examines a world <strong>of</strong> noncompulsory<br />

Prisoner's Dilemma games (if you don't fancy a particular<br />

opponent, you can decline to play ). Kitcher shows, in careful ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

detail, how "discriminating altruists" (who keep a tally on who has defected<br />

in <strong>the</strong> past) can flourish under certain—not all—conditions, <strong>and</strong> also begins<br />

to sort out <strong>the</strong> conditions under which varying policies <strong>of</strong> forgiveness <strong>and</strong><br />

forgetfulness can hold <strong>the</strong>ir own against <strong>the</strong> ever-present prospect <strong>of</strong> a<br />

resurgence <strong>of</strong> antisocial types. Particularly fascinating in <strong>the</strong> directions<br />

opened up by Kitcher's analysis is <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> groups in which <strong>the</strong><br />

strong <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> weak would tend to segregate <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> prefer to<br />

cooperate with <strong>the</strong>ir own sort.<br />

Could this set <strong>the</strong> stage for something like <strong>the</strong> Nietzschean transvaluation<br />

<strong>of</strong> values? Stranger things have happened. Stephen White (unpublished) has<br />

begun to investigate <strong>the</strong> important fur<strong>the</strong>r complexities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> multi-person<br />

Prisoner's Dilemma. (This is <strong>the</strong> game that leads to <strong>the</strong> tragedy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

commons, creating both depleted fish stocks in our oceans <strong>and</strong> forests <strong>of</strong> tall<br />

trees.) As Kitcher points out, <strong>the</strong> simple scenarios are analytically tractable—<br />

<strong>the</strong> equations <strong>of</strong> interaction <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir expected yields can be solved directly<br />

by ma<strong>the</strong>matical calculation—but as we add more realism, <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

complexity, <strong>the</strong> direct solution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> equations becomes unfeasible, so we<br />

have to turn to <strong>the</strong> indirect methods <strong>of</strong> computer simulation. In such a<br />

simulation, you just set up hundreds or thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> imaginary individuals,<br />

endow <strong>the</strong>m with dozens or hundreds or thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> strategies or o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

properties, <strong>and</strong> let <strong>the</strong> computer do all <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> having <strong>the</strong>m play thous<strong>and</strong>s<br />

or millions <strong>of</strong> games against each o<strong>the</strong>r, keeping track <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> results. 9<br />

This is a branch <strong>of</strong> sociobiology or evolutionary ethics that no one should<br />

deride. It directly tests <strong>the</strong> hunches, such as those <strong>of</strong> Hobbes <strong>and</strong> Nietzsche,<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re are natural, evolutionarily enforceable paths to where we are<br />

today. We may be quite sure that this is true, for here we are, but what this<br />

research promises to clarify is how much R-<strong>and</strong>-D work, <strong>of</strong> what sorts, was<br />

9. If you want to know <strong>the</strong> odds <strong>of</strong> being dealt a straight flush in poker, one way is to solve<br />

<strong>the</strong> equation provided by probability <strong>the</strong>ory; you get a definitive answer. Ano<strong>the</strong>r way is<br />

to deal yourself a few billion poker h<strong>and</strong>s, shuffling well between each, <strong>and</strong> simply<br />

counting <strong>the</strong> straight flushes <strong>and</strong> dividing by <strong>the</strong> total number <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s dealt. That gives<br />

you a very reliable estimate, but it is not <strong>of</strong>ficially foolpro<strong>of</strong>. The latter method is <strong>the</strong> only<br />

feasible way to study <strong>the</strong> complicated scenarios <strong>of</strong> evolutionary ethics, but, as we already<br />

saw in <strong>the</strong> discussion (in chapter 7 ) <strong>of</strong> Conway's reactions to <strong>the</strong> ways in which his Game<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Life</strong> is being explored, <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> such simulations can be misleading, <strong>and</strong> should<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten be taken with a grain <strong>of</strong> salt.<br />

Sociobiology: Good <strong>and</strong> Bad, Good <strong>and</strong> Evil 481<br />

required to get us here. At one extreme, it could turn out that <strong>the</strong>re is an<br />

impressive bottleneck; a quite improbable but crucial series <strong>of</strong> happy accidents<br />

were required. (White's analysis <strong>of</strong>fers some plausible reasons for<br />

believing that <strong>the</strong> conditions are really quite stringent.) At <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r extreme<br />

it might turn out that <strong>the</strong>re is a ra<strong>the</strong>r wide "basin <strong>of</strong> attraction" that will lead<br />

almost any cognitively sophisticated creatures, whatever <strong>the</strong>ir circumstances,<br />

into societies with recognizable ethical codes. It will be fascinating to see<br />

what large-scale computer simulations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se complex social interactions<br />

tell us about <strong>the</strong> constraints on <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> ethics. But we can already be<br />

virtually certain that mutual recognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> capacity to communicate a<br />

promise—stressed by both Hobbes <strong>and</strong> Nietzsche—are necessary conditions<br />

for <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> morality. It is conceivable if unlikely on present<br />

evidence, that whales <strong>and</strong> dolphins, or <strong>the</strong> great apes, meet <strong>the</strong>se necessary<br />

conditions, but no o<strong>the</strong>r species come close to exhibiting <strong>the</strong> sorts <strong>of</strong> social<br />

cognition that true morality depends on. (My pessimistic hunch is that <strong>the</strong><br />

main reason we haven't yet ruled out dolphins <strong>and</strong> whales as moralists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

deep is that <strong>the</strong>y are so hard to study in <strong>the</strong> wild. Most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> evidence about<br />

<strong>the</strong> chimpanzees—some <strong>of</strong> it self-censored by researchers for years—is that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are true denizens <strong>of</strong> Hobbes' state <strong>of</strong> nature, much more nasty <strong>and</strong><br />

brutish than many would like to believe.)<br />

4. SOCIOBIOLOGY: GOOD AND BAD, GOOD AND EVIL<br />

... <strong>the</strong> human brain works however it works. Wishing for it to work in<br />

some way as a shortcut to justifying some ethical principle undermines<br />

both <strong>the</strong> science <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ethics (for what happens to <strong>the</strong> principle if <strong>the</strong><br />

scientific facts turn out to go <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way?).<br />

—STEVEN PINKER 1994, p. 427<br />

Sociobiology has two faces. One looks toward <strong>the</strong> social behavior <strong>of</strong><br />

nonhuman animals. The eyes are carefully focused, <strong>the</strong> lips pursed<br />

judiciously. Utterances are made only with caution. The o<strong>the</strong>r face is<br />

almost hidden behind a megaphone. With great excitement, pronouncements<br />

about human nature blare forth.<br />

—PHIUP KITCHER 1985b, p. 435<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r part <strong>of</strong> our inquiry into human nature, as a naturalistic basis for<br />

sound ethical thinking, would begin with <strong>the</strong> undisputable fact that we<br />

human beings are products <strong>of</strong> evolution, <strong>and</strong> consider what limitations we<br />

are born with <strong>and</strong> what variations <strong>the</strong>re are among us that might have ethical<br />

relevance. Many people apparently think that ethics is in deep trou-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!