21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

192 BIOLOGY IS ENGINEERING Darwin Is Dead—Long Live Darwin! 193<br />

nonical or wild-type text <strong>of</strong> that work was, but <strong>the</strong> identity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work would<br />

hardly be in jeopardy. James Joyce's Ulysses would be a good case in point.)<br />

Eigen points out that this distribution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> "essence" over a variety <strong>of</strong><br />

nearly identical vehicles turns out to make that essence much more movable,<br />

much more adaptable, especially in "rugged" fitness l<strong>and</strong>scapes, with<br />

multiple peaks <strong>and</strong> few smooth slopes. It permits <strong>the</strong> essence to send out<br />

efficient scouting parties into <strong>the</strong> neighboring hills <strong>and</strong> ridges, ignoring<br />

wasteful exploration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> valleys, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby vastly (not Vastly, but<br />

enough to make a huge difference) enhancing its capacity to find higher<br />

peaks, better optima, at some distance from its center, where <strong>the</strong> (virtual)<br />

wild type sits. 1<br />

The reasons it works are summarized by Eigen as follows:<br />

Functionally competent mutants, whose selection values come close to<br />

that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wild type (though remaining below it), reach far higher population<br />

numbers than those that are functionally ineffective. An asymmetric<br />

spectrum <strong>of</strong> mutants builds up, in which mutants far removed from <strong>the</strong><br />

wild type arise successively from intermediates. The population in such a<br />

chain <strong>of</strong> mutants is influenced decisively by <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> value<br />

l<strong>and</strong>scape. The value l<strong>and</strong>scape consists <strong>of</strong> connected plains, hills, <strong>and</strong><br />

mountain ranges. In <strong>the</strong> mountain ranges, <strong>the</strong> mutant spectrum is widely<br />

scattered, <strong>and</strong> along ridges even distant relatives <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wild type appear<br />

with finite [that is, not infinitesimal] frequency. It is precisely in <strong>the</strong> mountainous<br />

regions that fur<strong>the</strong>r selectively superior mutants can be expected.<br />

As soon as one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se turns up on <strong>the</strong> periphery <strong>of</strong> a mutation spectrum<br />

<strong>the</strong> established ensemble collapses. A new ensemble builds up around <strong>the</strong><br />

superior mutant, which thus takes over <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wild type___ This<br />

causal chain results in a kind <strong>of</strong> 'mass action', by which <strong>the</strong> superior mutants<br />

are tested with much higher probability than inferior mutants, even<br />

if <strong>the</strong> latter are an equal distance away from <strong>the</strong> wild type. [Eigen 1992,<br />

p. 25.]<br />

So <strong>the</strong>re is a tight interaction between <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fitness l<strong>and</strong>scape<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> population that occupies it, creating a series <strong>of</strong> feedback loops,<br />

1. The similarity between <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>mes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>mes I develop in Consciousness<br />

Explained (1991a) about <strong>the</strong> need to break up <strong>the</strong> Cartesian Theater, with its Central<br />

Meaner, <strong>and</strong> distribute its intelligence work around to a variety <strong>of</strong> peripheral agents, is <strong>of</strong><br />

course no accident. It is, however, mainly a case <strong>of</strong> convergent evolution, so far as I can<br />

determine. I had not read any <strong>of</strong> Eigen's work at <strong>the</strong> time I was writing my book, though<br />

it certainly would have inspired me if I had. A useful bridge between Eigen on molecules<br />

<strong>and</strong> me on consciousness is Schull 1990 on <strong>the</strong> intelligence <strong>of</strong> species, <strong>and</strong> my commentary,<br />

Dennett 1990a.<br />

leading—usually—from one temporarily stable problem-setting to ano<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

No sooner do you climb a peak than <strong>the</strong> whole l<strong>and</strong>scape pitches <strong>and</strong> billows<br />

into a new mountain range <strong>and</strong> you start climbing all over again. In fact, <strong>the</strong><br />

l<strong>and</strong>scape is constantly shifting under your feet (if you are a quasi-species <strong>of</strong><br />

viruses ).<br />

Now, this is really not as revolutionary as Eigen claims. Sewall Wright<br />

himself, in his "shirting balance <strong>the</strong>ory," tried to explain how multiple peaks<br />

<strong>and</strong> shifting l<strong>and</strong>scapes would be traversable not by individual "wild-type"<br />

exemplars, but by various-sized populations <strong>of</strong> variants, <strong>and</strong> Ernst Mayr has<br />

stressed for many years that "population thinking" is at <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> Darwinism,<br />

something overlooked by geneticists at <strong>the</strong>ir peril. So Eigen has<br />

really not revolutionized Darwinism but, ra<strong>the</strong>r—no small contribution—<br />

created some <strong>the</strong>oretical innovations that clarify <strong>and</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>n underappreciated<br />

<strong>and</strong> imperfectly formulated ideas that had been around for years.<br />

When Eigen (1992, p. 125) says, "The (quantitative) acceleration <strong>of</strong> evolution<br />

that this brings about is so great that it appears to <strong>the</strong> biologist as a surprising<br />

new quality, an apparent ability <strong>of</strong> selection to 'see ahead', something that<br />

would be viewed by classical Darwinians as <strong>the</strong> purest heresy!" he is<br />

indulging in a familiar form <strong>of</strong> overdramatization, ignoring <strong>the</strong> many<br />

biologists who at least anticipated, <strong>and</strong> perhaps even fomented, his "revolution."<br />

After all, when traditional Darwinian <strong>the</strong>orists postulate fitness l<strong>and</strong>scapes<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n r<strong>and</strong>omly sprinkle genotypes on <strong>the</strong>m in order to calculate what<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory says would happen to <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>the</strong>y know that, in nature, genotypes don't<br />

just get thrown r<strong>and</strong>omly into pre-existing parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. Every model <strong>of</strong><br />

a time-consuming process has to start at some arbitrary "moment"; <strong>the</strong> curtain<br />

rises <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> model <strong>the</strong>n plots what happens next. If we look at such a model<br />

<strong>and</strong> see that at <strong>the</strong> "outset" it shows a bunch <strong>of</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates down in <strong>the</strong><br />

valleys, we can be pretty sure that <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orist recognizes that <strong>the</strong>y weren't<br />

"always" down <strong>the</strong>re—whatever that would mean! Wherever on <strong>the</strong> fitness<br />

l<strong>and</strong>scape <strong>the</strong>re are c<strong>and</strong>idates at one time, <strong>the</strong>re were peaks before, or those<br />

c<strong>and</strong>idates wouldn't be <strong>the</strong>re, so <strong>the</strong>se must be relatively new valleys <strong>the</strong>se<br />

c<strong>and</strong>idates are occupying, a new predicament that evolution has placed before<br />

<strong>the</strong>m. Only that assumption could justify locating <strong>the</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates in <strong>the</strong><br />

valleys in <strong>the</strong> first place. Eigen's contribution reinforces <strong>the</strong> appreciation that<br />

we have to add <strong>the</strong>se complications to <strong>the</strong> models if we want <strong>the</strong>m actually to<br />

do <strong>the</strong> work that Darwinians have always supposed that <strong>the</strong>ir simpler models<br />

could do.<br />

It is certainly no accident that our appreciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> need for <strong>the</strong>se much<br />

more complicated models coincides in time (almost down to <strong>the</strong> month, <strong>and</strong><br />

certainly to <strong>the</strong> year) with our capacity to build <strong>and</strong> explore such models on<br />

existing computers. No sooner do more powerful computers become<br />

available than we discover with <strong>the</strong>ir help that more complex

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!