21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

432 THE EMPEROR'S NEW MIND, AND OTHER FABLES<br />

human being from any machine, <strong>and</strong> he came up with "two very certain<br />

means":<br />

The first is that <strong>the</strong>y [<strong>the</strong> machines] could never use words, or put toge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r signs, as we do in order to declare our thoughts to o<strong>the</strong>rs. For we can<br />

certainly conceive <strong>of</strong> a machine so constructed that it utters words, <strong>and</strong><br />

even utters words which correspond to bodily actions causing a change in<br />

its organs (e.g., if you touch it in one spot it asks what you want <strong>of</strong> it, if you<br />

touch it in ano<strong>the</strong>r it cries out that you are hurting it, <strong>and</strong> so on). But it is<br />

not conceivable that such a machine should produce different arrangements<br />

<strong>of</strong> words so as to give an appropriately meaningful answer to whatever<br />

is said in its presence, as <strong>the</strong> dullest <strong>of</strong> men can do. Secondly, even<br />

though such machines might do some things as well as we do <strong>the</strong>m, or<br />

perhaps even better, <strong>the</strong>y would inevitably fail in o<strong>the</strong>rs, which would<br />

reveal that <strong>the</strong>y were acting not through underst<strong>and</strong>ing but only from <strong>the</strong><br />

disposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir organs. For whereas reason is a universal instrument<br />

which can be used in all kinds <strong>of</strong> situations, <strong>the</strong>se organs need some<br />

particular disposition for each particular action; hence it is for all practical<br />

purposes impossible for a machine to have enough different organs to<br />

make it act in all <strong>the</strong> contingencies <strong>of</strong> life in <strong>the</strong> way in which our reason<br />

makes us act. [Descartes 1637, pt. 5.]<br />

Alan Turing, in 1950, asked himself <strong>the</strong> same question, <strong>and</strong> came up with<br />

just <strong>the</strong> same acid test—somewhat more rigorously described—what he<br />

called <strong>the</strong> imitation game, <strong>and</strong> we now call <strong>the</strong> Turing Test. Put two contestants—one<br />

human, one a computer—in boxes (in effect) <strong>and</strong> conduct<br />

conversations with each; if <strong>the</strong> computer can convince you it is <strong>the</strong> human<br />

being, it wins <strong>the</strong> imitation game. Turing's verdict, however, was strikingly<br />

different from Descartes's:<br />

I believe that in about fifty years' time it will be possible to program<br />

computers, with a storage capacity <strong>of</strong> about 10 9 , to make <strong>the</strong>m play <strong>the</strong><br />

imitation game so well that an average interrogator will not have more<br />

than a 70 percent chance <strong>of</strong> making <strong>the</strong> right identification after five minutes<br />

<strong>of</strong> questioning. The original question, 'Can machines think?' I believe<br />

to be too meaningless to deserve discussion. Never<strong>the</strong>less I believe that at<br />

<strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> century <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> words <strong>and</strong> general educated opinion will<br />

have altered so much that one will be able to speak <strong>of</strong> machines thinking<br />

without expecting to be contradicted. [Turing 1950, p. 435.]<br />

Turing has already been proven right about his last prophecy: "<strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong><br />

words <strong>and</strong> general educated opinion" has already "altered so much" that one<br />

can speak <strong>of</strong> machines thinking without expecting to be contradicted— "on<br />

general principles." Descartes found <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> a thinking machine<br />

The Sword in <strong>the</strong> Stone 433<br />

"innconceivable," <strong>and</strong> even if, as many today believe, no machine will ever<br />

succeed in passing <strong>the</strong> Turing Test, almost no one today would claim that <strong>the</strong><br />

very idea is inconceivable. Perhaps this sea-change in public opinion has<br />

been helped along by <strong>the</strong> comouter's progress on o<strong>the</strong>r feats, such as playing<br />

checkers <strong>and</strong> chess. In an address in 1957, Herbert Simon (Simon <strong>and</strong><br />

Newell 1958) predicted that computer would be <strong>the</strong> world chess champion in<br />

less than a decade, a classic case <strong>of</strong> overoptimism, as it turns out. A few<br />

years later, <strong>the</strong> philosopher Hubert Dreyfus (1965) predicted that no<br />

computer would ever be able to play good chess, since playing chess<br />

required "insight," but he himself was soon trounced at chess by a computer<br />

program, an occasion for much glee among AI researchers. Art Samuel's<br />

checkers program has been followed by literally hundreds <strong>of</strong> chess-playing<br />

programs, which now compete in tournaments against both human <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

computer contestants, <strong>and</strong> will probably soon be able to beat <strong>the</strong> best human<br />

chess players in <strong>the</strong><br />

world.<br />

But is chess-playing a suitable "sword-in-<strong>the</strong>-stone" test? Dreyfus may<br />

once have thought so, <strong>and</strong> he has a distinguished predecessor—Edgar Allan<br />

Poe, <strong>of</strong> all people—whose certainty on this score drove him to unmask one<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> great hoaxes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nineteenth century, von Kempelen's chess "automaton."<br />

In <strong>the</strong> eighteenth century, <strong>the</strong> great Vaucanson had made mechanical<br />

marvels that entranced <strong>the</strong> nobility, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r paying customers, by<br />

exhibiting behaviors that even today inspire our skepticism. Could Vaucanson's<br />

clockwork duck really do what it is reported to have done? "When<br />

corn was thrown down before it, <strong>the</strong> duck stretched out its neck to pick it up,<br />

swallowed, <strong>and</strong> digested it" (Poe 1836a, p. 1255). O<strong>the</strong>r ingenious artificers<br />

<strong>and</strong> tricksters had followed in Vaucanson's wake, developing <strong>the</strong> art <strong>of</strong><br />

mechanical simulacra to such a high pitch that one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, Baron von<br />

Kempelen, in 1769, could exploit public fascination with such devices by<br />

creating a deliberate tease: a purported automaton that could play chess.<br />

Von Kempelen's original machine passed into <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Johann Nepomuk<br />

Maelzel, 1 who made some improvements <strong>and</strong> revisions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n<br />

caused quite a stir in <strong>the</strong> early nineteenth century by exhibiting Maelzel's<br />

Chess-Machine, never quite guaranteeing that it was just a machine, <strong>and</strong><br />

surrounding <strong>the</strong> whole performance (for which he charged a pretty penny )<br />

with enough <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard magician's ostentations to arouse anybody's<br />

1. This same Maelzel is <strong>the</strong> inventor (or perfecter) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> metronome, <strong>and</strong> made <strong>the</strong> ear<br />

tnumpet that Beethoven relied on for years, once he began to go deaf. Maelzel also<br />

created a mechanical orchestra, <strong>the</strong> Panharmonicon, for which Beethoven wrote Wellington's<br />

Victory, but <strong>the</strong> two had a falling out over property rights to that composition—<br />

Maelzel was both a crane-maker <strong>and</strong> crane-stealer <strong>of</strong> great talent.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!