21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

378 LOSING OUR MINDS TO DARWIN The Role <strong>of</strong> Language in Intelligence 379<br />

enough to be given <strong>the</strong> tool. The better designed <strong>the</strong> tool (<strong>the</strong> more information<br />

embedded in its fabrication), <strong>the</strong> more Potential Intelligence it<br />

confers on its user. And among <strong>the</strong> pre-eminent tools, Gregory reminds us,<br />

are what he calls "mind-tools": words.<br />

Gregorian creature imports mind-tools<br />

from <strong>the</strong> (cultural) environment; <strong>the</strong>se<br />

improve both <strong>the</strong> generators <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

testers.<br />

FIGURE 13.4<br />

Words <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r mind-tools give a Gregorian creature an inner environment<br />

that permits it to construct ever more subtle move-generators <strong>and</strong><br />

move-testers. Skinnerian creatures ask <strong>the</strong>mselves, "What do I do next?" <strong>and</strong><br />

haven't a clue how to answer until <strong>the</strong>y have taken some hard knocks.<br />

Popperian creatures make a big advance by asking <strong>the</strong>mselves, "What should<br />

I think about next?" before <strong>the</strong>y ask <strong>the</strong>mselves, "What should I do next?"<br />

Gregorian creatures take a fur<strong>the</strong>r big step by learning how to think better<br />

about what <strong>the</strong>y should think about next—<strong>and</strong> so forth, a tower <strong>of</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

internal reflections with no fixed or discernible limit.<br />

What happens to a human or hominid brain when it becomes equipped<br />

with words? In particular, what is <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> this environment when words<br />

first enter it? It is definitely not an even playing field or a tabula rasa. Our<br />

newfound words must anchor <strong>the</strong>mselves on <strong>the</strong> hills <strong>and</strong> valleys <strong>of</strong> a<br />

l<strong>and</strong>scape <strong>of</strong> considerable complexity. Thanks to earlier evolutionary pressures,<br />

our innate quality spaces are species-specific, narcissistic, <strong>and</strong> even<br />

idiosyncratic from individual to individual. A number <strong>of</strong> investigators are<br />

currently exploring portions <strong>of</strong> this terrain. The psychologist Frank Keil<br />

(1992) <strong>and</strong> his colleagues at Cornell have evidence that certain highly<br />

abstract concepts—such as <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong> being alive or ownership, for<br />

instance—have a genetically imposed head start in <strong>the</strong> young child's kit <strong>of</strong><br />

mind-tools; when <strong>the</strong> specific words for owning, giving <strong>and</strong> taking, keeping<br />

<strong>and</strong> hiding, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir kin enter a child's brain, <strong>the</strong>y find homes already<br />

partially built for <strong>the</strong>m. Ray Jackend<strong>of</strong>f (1993) <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r linguists have<br />

identified fundamental structures <strong>of</strong> spatial representation—notably designed<br />

to enhance <strong>the</strong> control <strong>of</strong> locomotion <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> placement <strong>of</strong> movable things—<br />

that underlie our intuitions about concepts like beside, on, behind, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

kin. Nicholas Humphrey (1976,1983,1986) has argued that <strong>the</strong>re must be a<br />

genetic predisposition for adopting <strong>the</strong> intentional stance, <strong>and</strong> Alan Leslie<br />

(1992 ) <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs have developed evidence for this, in <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> what he<br />

calls a "<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> mind module" designed to generate second-order beliefs<br />

(beliefs about <strong>the</strong> beliefs <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r mental states <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs). Some autistic<br />

children seem to be well described as suffering from <strong>the</strong> disabling <strong>of</strong> this<br />

module, for which <strong>the</strong>y can occasionally make interesting compensatory<br />

adjustments. (For an overview, see Baron-Cohen 1995.) So <strong>the</strong> words (<strong>and</strong><br />

hence memes) that take up residence in a brain, like so many earlier design<br />

novelties we have considered, enhance <strong>and</strong> shape pre-existing structures,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than generating entirely new architectures (see Sperber [in press] for a<br />

Darwinian overview <strong>of</strong> this exaptation <strong>of</strong> genetically provided functions by<br />

culturally transmitted functions). Though <strong>the</strong>se newly redesigned functions<br />

are not made from whole cloth, <strong>the</strong>y do create an explosive new capacity to<br />

look ahead.<br />

An internal model allows a system to look ahead to <strong>the</strong> future consequences<br />

<strong>of</strong> current actions, without actually committing itself to those<br />

actions. In particular, <strong>the</strong> system can avoid acts that would set it irretrievably<br />

down some road to future disaster ("stepping <strong>of</strong>f a cliff"). Less dramatically,<br />

but equally important, <strong>the</strong> model enables <strong>the</strong> agent to make<br />

current "stage-setting" moves that set up later moves that are obviously<br />

advantageous. The very essence <strong>of</strong> a competitive advantage, whe<strong>the</strong>r it be<br />

in chess or economics, is <strong>the</strong> discovery <strong>and</strong> execution <strong>of</strong> stage-setting<br />

moves. [Holl<strong>and</strong> 1992, p. 25.]<br />

This, <strong>the</strong>n, is <strong>the</strong> crane to end all cranes: an explorer that does have<br />

foresight, that can see beyond <strong>the</strong> immediate neighborhood <strong>of</strong> options. But<br />

how good can <strong>the</strong> "stage-setting" be without <strong>the</strong> intervention <strong>of</strong> language to<br />

help control <strong>the</strong> manipulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> model? How intricate <strong>and</strong> long-range can<br />

<strong>the</strong> look-ahead be, for instance? This is <strong>the</strong> relevance <strong>of</strong> my question about<br />

<strong>the</strong> chimpanzee's capacities to visualize a novel scene. Darwin (1871, p. 57 )<br />

was convinced that language was <strong>the</strong> prerequisite for "long trains <strong>of</strong> thought,"<br />

<strong>and</strong> this claim has been differently supported by several recent <strong>the</strong>orists,<br />

especially Julian Jaynes (1976) <strong>and</strong> Howard Margolis (1987). Long trains <strong>of</strong><br />

thought have to be controlled, or <strong>the</strong>y will w<strong>and</strong>er <strong>of</strong>f into delicious if futile<br />

woolga<strong>the</strong>ring. These authors suggest, plausibly, that <strong>the</strong> self-exhortations<br />

<strong>and</strong> reminders made possible by language are actually

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!