21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

296 BULLY FOR BRONTOSAURUS<br />

from ever being gr<strong>and</strong>parents could hardly make a difference to how <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

contemporaries got sorted out by selective pressure. That would require some<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> backward-in-time causation.<br />

Is this really true? You may think that this would be true if <strong>the</strong> event that<br />

kicked <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> speciation was a geographic split, guaranteeing <strong>the</strong> complete<br />

causal isolation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two groups (allopatric speciation), but what if <strong>the</strong><br />

speciation got under way within a population that formed two reproduc-tively<br />

incommunicative subgroups that competed directly against each o<strong>the</strong>r (in a<br />

form <strong>of</strong> sympatric speciation)? Darwin proposed, as we noted (see page 43),<br />

that competition between closely related forms would be a driving force in<br />

speciation, so <strong>the</strong> presence—<strong>the</strong> nonabsence—<strong>of</strong> what can be retrospectively<br />

identified as <strong>the</strong> first generations <strong>of</strong> a "rival" species might be very important<br />

indeed for speciation, but <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se rivals are "going to be" <strong>the</strong><br />

founders <strong>of</strong> a new species could not play a role in <strong>the</strong> intensity or o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> competition <strong>and</strong> hence in <strong>the</strong> speed or direction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

horizontal motion in Design Space.<br />

We may well suppose that relatively rapid morphological change (sideways<br />

movement) is a normally necessary precondition for speciation. Rapidity <strong>of</strong><br />

change is crucially affected by <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gene pool; large gene pools are<br />

conservative <strong>and</strong> tend to absorb innovation attempts without a trace. One way<br />

<strong>of</strong> making a large gene pool small is dividing it in two, <strong>and</strong> this may in fact be<br />

<strong>the</strong> most common sort <strong>of</strong> downsizing, but <strong>the</strong>reafter it makes no difference<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r or not nature discards one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> halves (as in <strong>the</strong> middle graph in<br />

figure 10.11). It is <strong>the</strong> bottleneck <strong>of</strong> a diminished gene pool that permits <strong>the</strong><br />

rapid motion, not <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> two or more different bottlenecks. If <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

speciation, <strong>the</strong>n two whole species pass through <strong>the</strong>ir respective bottlenecks; if<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no speciation, <strong>the</strong>n one whole species is pressed through a single<br />

bottleneck. So cladogenesis cannot involve a process during a punctuation<br />

period different from <strong>the</strong> process that occurs in anagenesis, because <strong>the</strong><br />

difference between cladogenesis <strong>and</strong> anagenesis is definable only in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

postpunctuation sequelae. Gould sometimes speaks as if speciation does make<br />

a difference. For instance, Gould <strong>and</strong> Eldredge (1993, p. 225) speak <strong>of</strong> "<strong>the</strong><br />

crucial requirement <strong>of</strong> ancestral survival after punctuated branching" (as<br />

shown on <strong>the</strong> left in figure 10.11), but according to Eldredge (personal<br />

communication) this is only a crucial epistemological requirement for <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>orist, who needs "ancestral survival" as evidence <strong>of</strong> descent.<br />

His explanation is interesting. The fossil record is loaded with cases in<br />

which one form abruptly stops <strong>and</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r, quite different, form abruptly<br />

appears "in its place." Which <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se are cases <strong>of</strong> swift sideways leaps <strong>of</strong><br />

evolution, <strong>and</strong> which are cases <strong>of</strong> simple displacement due to sudden immigration<br />

<strong>of</strong> a ra<strong>the</strong>r distant relative? You can't tell. It is only when you can<br />

see what you take to be <strong>the</strong> parent species coexisting for a while with what<br />

Punctuated Equilibrium: A Hopeful Monster 297<br />

you take to be its <strong>of</strong>fspring that you can be quite sure that <strong>the</strong>re is a direct path<br />

from <strong>the</strong> earlier form to <strong>the</strong> later form. As an epistemological point, this<br />

completely undercuts <strong>the</strong> claim that Gould has wanted to make: that most<br />

swift evolutionary change has been accomplished by speciation. For if, as<br />

Eldredge says, <strong>the</strong> fossil record usually shows abrupt shifts without any<br />

"ancestral survival after punctuated branching," <strong>and</strong> if <strong>the</strong>re is no telling<br />

which <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se are cases <strong>of</strong> punctuated anagenetic change (as opposed to<br />

immigration phenomena), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is no way <strong>of</strong> telling from <strong>the</strong> fossil<br />

record whe<strong>the</strong>r speciation is a very frequent or very rare accompaniment <strong>of</strong><br />

rapid morphological change. 7<br />

There might still be ano<strong>the</strong>r way <strong>of</strong> making sense <strong>of</strong> Gould's insistence that it is<br />

speciation, not mere adaptation, that makes <strong>the</strong> big difference in evolution.<br />

What if it turned out that some lineages go in for a lot <strong>of</strong> punctuation (<strong>and</strong>, in<br />

<strong>the</strong> process, produce lots <strong>of</strong> daughter species) <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r lineages do not, <strong>and</strong><br />

those that do not do so tend to die out? Neo-Darwinians usually assume that<br />

adaptations occur by <strong>the</strong> gradual transformation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> organisms in particular<br />

lineages, but "if lineages do not change by transformation, <strong>the</strong>n long term trends<br />

in lineages can hardly be <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir slow transformation" (Sterelny 1992,<br />

p. 48). This has long been considered an interesting possibility (in <strong>the</strong>ir original<br />

article, Eldredge <strong>and</strong> Gould discuss it very briefly, <strong>and</strong> credit Sewall Wright<br />

1967 as one <strong>of</strong> its sources). Gould's version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> idea (e.g., 1982a) is that<br />

whole species don't get revised by <strong>the</strong> piecemeal redesign <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir individual<br />

members; species are ra<strong>the</strong>r brittle, unchanging things; <strong>the</strong> shifts in Design<br />

Space happen (largely? <strong>of</strong>ten? always?) because <strong>of</strong> species extinction <strong>and</strong><br />

species birth. This idea is what Gould <strong>and</strong> Eldredge (1993, p. 224) call "higher<br />

level sorting." It is sometimes known as species selection, or clade selection. It<br />

is hard to get clear about, but we have <strong>the</strong> equipment already at h<strong>and</strong> to clarify<br />

its central point. Remember bait-<strong>and</strong>-switch? Gould is in effect proposing a new<br />

application <strong>of</strong> this fundamental Darwinian idea: don't think that evolution makes<br />

adjustments in existing lineages; evolution throws away whole lineages, <strong>and</strong> lets<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r, different, lineages prosper. It looks as if <strong>the</strong>re are adjustments to lineages<br />

over time, but what is really going on is bait-<strong>and</strong>-switch at <strong>the</strong> species level. The<br />

right level at which to look for evolutionary trends, he could <strong>the</strong>n claim, is not<br />

<strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gene, or <strong>the</strong> organism, but <strong>the</strong> whole species or clade. Instead <strong>of</strong><br />

looking at <strong>the</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> particular genes from gene pools, or <strong>the</strong> differential death<br />

<strong>of</strong> particular genotypes within a<br />

7. For a similar criticism <strong>of</strong> Gould, see Ayala 1982. See also G. Williams 1992, pp. 53-<br />

54; Williams, who defines cladogenesis as <strong>the</strong> isolation, however short-lived, <strong>of</strong> any<br />

gene pool, also points out <strong>the</strong> triviality to evolutionary <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> short-term cladogenesis<br />

(pp. 98-100).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!