21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

172 PRIMING DARWIN'S PUMP The Laws <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Game <strong>of</strong> <strong>Life</strong> 173<br />

in 1957. Francis Crick <strong>and</strong> James Watson had discovered DNA in 1953, but<br />

how it worked was a mystery for many years. Von Neumann had imagined<br />

in some detail a sort <strong>of</strong> floating robot that picked up pieces <strong>of</strong> flotsam <strong>and</strong><br />

jetsam that could be used to build a duplicate <strong>of</strong> itself that would <strong>the</strong>n be<br />

able to repeat <strong>the</strong> process. His description (posthumously published, 1966)<br />

<strong>of</strong> how an automaton would read its own blueprint <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n copy it into its<br />

new creation anticipated in impressive detail many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> later discoveries<br />

about <strong>the</strong> mechanisms <strong>of</strong> DNA expression <strong>and</strong> replication, but in order to<br />

make his pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> die possibility <strong>of</strong> a self-reproducing automaton ma<strong>the</strong>matically<br />

rigorous <strong>and</strong> tractable, von Neumann had switched to simple, twodimensional<br />

abstractions, now known as cellular automata. Conway's <strong>Life</strong>world<br />

cells are a particularly agreeable example <strong>of</strong> cellular automata.<br />

Conway <strong>and</strong> his students wanted to confirm von Neumann's pro<strong>of</strong> in<br />

detail by actually constructing a two-dimensional world with a simple physics<br />

in which such a self-replicating construction would be a stable, working<br />

structure. Like von Neumann, <strong>the</strong>y wanted <strong>the</strong>ir answer to be as general as<br />

possible, <strong>and</strong> hence as independent as possible <strong>of</strong> actual (Earthly? local?)<br />

physics <strong>and</strong> chemistry. They wanted something dead simple, easy to visualize<br />

<strong>and</strong> easy to calculate, so <strong>the</strong>y not only dropped from three dimensions<br />

to two; <strong>the</strong>y also "digitized" both space <strong>and</strong> time—all times <strong>and</strong> distances,<br />

as we saw, are in whole numbers <strong>of</strong> "instants" <strong>and</strong> "cells." It was von<br />

Neumann who had taken Alan Turing's abstract conception <strong>of</strong> a mechanical<br />

computer (now called a "Turing machine") <strong>and</strong> engineered it into <strong>the</strong><br />

specification for a general-purpose stored-program serial-processing<br />

computer (now called a "von Neumann machine"); in his brilliant<br />

explorations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spatial <strong>and</strong> structural requirements for such a computer,<br />

he had realized—<strong>and</strong> proved—that a Universal Turing machine (a Turing<br />

machine that can compute any computable function at all) could in principle<br />

be "built" in a two-dimensional world. 6 Conway <strong>and</strong> his students also set out<br />

to confirm this with <strong>the</strong>ir own exercise in two-dimensional engineering. 7<br />

It was far from easy, but <strong>the</strong>y showed how <strong>the</strong>y could "build" a working<br />

computer out <strong>of</strong> simpler <strong>Life</strong> forms. Glider streams can provide <strong>the</strong> inputoutput<br />

"tape," for instance, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> tape-reader can be some huge assembly<br />

<strong>of</strong> eaters, gliders, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r bits <strong>and</strong> pieces. What does this machine look<br />

like? Poundstone calculates that <strong>the</strong> whole construction would be on <strong>the</strong><br />

order <strong>of</strong> 10 13 cells or pads.<br />

6. See Dennett 1987b, ch. 9, for more on <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical implications <strong>of</strong> this trade-<strong>of</strong>f in<br />

space <strong>and</strong> time.<br />

7. For a completely different perspective on two-dimensional physics <strong>and</strong> engineering,<br />

see A. K. Dewdney's The Plantverse (1984 ), a vast improvement over Abbott's Flatl<strong>and</strong><br />

(1884).<br />

Displaying a 10 13 -pixel pattern would require a video screen about 3<br />

million pixels across at least. Assume <strong>the</strong> pixels are 1 millimeter square<br />

(which is very high resolution by <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>of</strong> home computers ). Then<br />

<strong>the</strong> screen would have to be 3 kilometers (about two miles) across. It<br />

would have an area about six times that <strong>of</strong> Monaco.<br />

Perspective would shrink <strong>the</strong> pixels <strong>of</strong> a self-reproducing pattern to<br />

invisibility. If you got far enough away from <strong>the</strong> screen so that <strong>the</strong> entire<br />

pattern was comfortably in view, <strong>the</strong> pixels (<strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong> gliders, eaters<br />

<strong>and</strong> guns) would be too tiny to make out. A self-reproducing pattern<br />

would be a hazy glow, like a galaxy. [Poundstone 1985, pp. 227-28.]<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, by <strong>the</strong> time you have built up enough pieces into something<br />

that can reproduce itself (in a two-dimensional world), it is roughly as<br />

much larger than its smallest bits as an organism is larger than its atoms. You<br />

probably can't do it with anything much less complicated, though this has not<br />

been strictly proven. The hunch with which we began this chapter gets<br />

dramatic support: it takes a lot <strong>of</strong> design work (<strong>the</strong> work done by Conway<br />

<strong>and</strong> his students) to turn available bits <strong>and</strong> pieces into a self-replicating<br />

thing; self-replicators don't just fall toge<strong>the</strong>r in cosmic coincidences; <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

too large <strong>and</strong> expensive.<br />

The Game <strong>of</strong> <strong>Life</strong> illustrates many important principles, <strong>and</strong> can be used to<br />

construct many different arguments or thought experiments, but I will<br />

content myself here with just two points that are particularly relevant to this<br />

stage in our argument, before turning to my main point. (For fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

reflections on <strong>Life</strong> <strong>and</strong> its implications, see Dennett 1991b.)<br />

First, notice how <strong>the</strong> distinction between Order <strong>and</strong> Design gets blurred<br />

here, just as it did for Hume. Conway designed <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>Life</strong> world—that is,<br />

he set out to articulate an Order that would function in a certain way. But do<br />

gliders, for instance, count as designed things, or as just natural objects—<br />

like atoms or molecules? Surely <strong>the</strong> tape-reader Conway <strong>and</strong> his students cobbled<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r out <strong>of</strong> gliders <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like is a designed object, but <strong>the</strong> simplest<br />

glider would seem just to fall out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> basic physics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Life</strong> world "automatically"—nobody<br />

had to design or invent <strong>the</strong> glider; it just was discovered<br />

to be implied by <strong>the</strong> physics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Life</strong> world. But that, <strong>of</strong> course, is<br />

actually true <strong>of</strong> everything in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Life</strong> world. Nothing happens in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Life</strong><br />

world that isn't strictly implied—logically deducible by straightforward<br />

<strong>the</strong>orem-proving—by <strong>the</strong> physics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> initial configuration <strong>of</strong> cells. Some<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> things in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Life</strong> world are just more marvelous <strong>and</strong> unanticipated ( by<br />

us, with our puny intellects) than o<strong>the</strong>rs. There is a sense in which <strong>the</strong> Conway<br />

self-reproducing pixel-galaxy is "just" one more <strong>Life</strong> macromolecule<br />

with a very long <strong>and</strong> complicated periodicity in its behavior.<br />

What if we set in motion a huge herd <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se self-reproducers, <strong>and</strong> let<br />

<strong>the</strong>m compete for resources. And suppose <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>n evolved—that is, <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

descendants were not exact duplicates <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Would <strong>the</strong>se descendants

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!