21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

326 CONTROVERSIES CONTAINED Cui Bono? 327<br />

9 <strong>of</strong> David Haig's sleuthing, but <strong>the</strong>re are hundreds or thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

that could be cited. (Cronin 1991 <strong>and</strong> Matt Ridley 1993 survey <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong><br />

this research up to <strong>the</strong> present.) Whenever you have an evolutionary puzzle,<br />

<strong>the</strong> gene's-eye perspective is apt to yield a solution in terms <strong>of</strong> some gene or<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r being favored for one reason or o<strong>the</strong>r. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as adaptations are<br />

manifestly for <strong>the</strong> good <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> organism (<strong>the</strong> eagle-as-organism surely<br />

benefits from its eagle-eye <strong>and</strong> eagle-wing), this is largely for <strong>the</strong> Wilsonian<br />

reason: what's good for <strong>the</strong> genes is good for <strong>the</strong> whole organism. But when<br />

push comes to shove, what's good for <strong>the</strong> genes determines what <strong>the</strong> future<br />

will hold. They are, after all, <strong>the</strong> replicators whose varying prospects in <strong>the</strong><br />

self-replication competitions set <strong>the</strong> whole process <strong>of</strong> evolution in motion,<br />

<strong>and</strong> keep it in motion.<br />

This perspective, sometimes called gene centrism, or <strong>the</strong> gene's-eye point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view, has provoked a great deal <strong>of</strong> criticism, much <strong>of</strong> it misguided. For<br />

instance, it is <strong>of</strong>ten said that gene centrism is "reductionistic." So it is, in <strong>the</strong><br />

good sense. That is, it shuns skyhooks, <strong>and</strong> insists that all lifting in Design<br />

Space must be done by cranes. But as we saw in chapter 3, sometimes people<br />

use "reductionism" to refer to <strong>the</strong> view that one should "reduce" all science,<br />

or all explanations, to some lowest level—<strong>the</strong> molecular level or <strong>the</strong> atomic<br />

or subatomic level (but probably nobody has ever espoused this variety <strong>of</strong><br />

reductionism, for it is manifestly silly). In any event, gene centrism is<br />

triumphantly non-reductionistic, in that sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term. What could be less<br />

reductionistic (in that sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term) than explaining <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong>, say,<br />

a particular amino-acid molecule in a particular location in a particular body<br />

by citing, not some o<strong>the</strong>r molecular-level facts, but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong><br />

body in question was a female in a species that provides prolonged care for<br />

its young? The gene's-eye point <strong>of</strong> view explains things in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

intricate interactions between long-range, large-scale ecological facts, longterm<br />

historical facts, <strong>and</strong> local, molecular-level facts.<br />

Natural selection is not a force that "acts" at one level—for instance, <strong>the</strong><br />

molecular level as opposed to <strong>the</strong> population level or organism level. Natural<br />

selection occurs because a sum <strong>of</strong> events, <strong>of</strong> all sorts <strong>and</strong> sizes, has a<br />

particular statistically describable outcome. The blue whale teeters on <strong>the</strong><br />

brink <strong>of</strong> extinction; if it goes extinct, a particularly magnificent <strong>and</strong> almost<br />

impossible to replace set <strong>of</strong> volumes in <strong>the</strong> Library <strong>of</strong> Mendel will cease to<br />

have extant copies, but <strong>the</strong> factor that best explains why those characteristic<br />

chromosomes, or collections <strong>of</strong> DNA nucleotide sequences, vanish from <strong>the</strong><br />

earth might be a virus that somehow directly attacked <strong>the</strong> DNA-replicating<br />

machinery in <strong>the</strong> whales, a stray comet l<strong>and</strong>ing near <strong>the</strong> pod <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> survivors<br />

at just <strong>the</strong> wrong time, or a surfeit <strong>of</strong> television publicity, causing curious<br />

humans to interfere catastrophically with <strong>the</strong>ir breeding habits! There is<br />

always a gene's-eye description <strong>of</strong> every evolutionary effect, but <strong>the</strong> more<br />

important question is whe<strong>the</strong>r such a description might <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

be mere "bookkeeping" (<strong>and</strong> as unilluminating as a molecular-level box score<br />

<strong>of</strong> a baseball game). William Wimsatt (1980) introduced <strong>the</strong> term<br />

"bookkeeping" to refer to <strong>the</strong> fact, agreed to on all sides, that <strong>the</strong> genes are<br />

<strong>the</strong> storehouse <strong>of</strong> information on genetic change, leaving it debatable whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>the</strong> gene-centered view was just bookkeeping, a charge that has <strong>of</strong>ten been<br />

made (e.g., by Gould 1992a). George Williams (1985, p. 4) accepts <strong>the</strong> label<br />

but vigorously defends <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> bookkeeping: "The idea that<br />

bookkeeping has been taking place in <strong>the</strong> past is what gives <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

natural selection its most important kind <strong>of</strong> predictive power." (See Buss<br />

1987, especially pp. 174ff., for important reflections on this<br />

claim.)<br />

The claim that <strong>the</strong> gene-centrist perspective is best, or most important, is<br />

not a claim about <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> molecular biology, but about something<br />

more abstract: about which level does <strong>the</strong> most explanatory work under most<br />

conditions. Philosophers <strong>of</strong> biology have paid more close attention, <strong>and</strong> made<br />

more substantive contributions, to <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> this issue than to any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

in evolutionary <strong>the</strong>ory. I have just mentioned Wimsatt, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re are o<strong>the</strong>rs—<br />

to pick just some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> best, David Hull ( 1980), Elliot Sober (1981a), <strong>and</strong><br />

Kim Sterelny <strong>and</strong> Philip Kitcher (1988). One reason philosophers have been<br />

attracted to <strong>the</strong> question is surely its ab-stractness <strong>and</strong> conceptual intricacy.<br />

Thinking about it soon gets you into deep questions about what it is to explain<br />

something, what causation is, what a level is, <strong>and</strong> so forth. This is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

brightest areas in recent philosophy <strong>of</strong> science; <strong>the</strong> scientists have paid<br />

respectful attention to <strong>the</strong>ir philosophical colleagues, <strong>and</strong> have had that<br />

attention repaid with knowledgeable <strong>and</strong> well-communicated analyses <strong>and</strong><br />

arguments by <strong>the</strong> philosophers, to which <strong>the</strong> scientists in turn have responded<br />

with discussions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>of</strong> more than workaday philosophical<br />

significance. It is a rich harvest, <strong>and</strong> I find it hard to tear myself away from it<br />

without giving a proper introduction to <strong>the</strong> subtleties in <strong>the</strong> issues, all <strong>the</strong><br />

more so because I have strongly held opinions about where <strong>the</strong> bulk <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

wisdom lies with <strong>the</strong>se controversies, but I have a different agenda here,<br />

which is, curiously enough, to drain <strong>the</strong> drama from <strong>the</strong>m. They are excellent<br />

scientific <strong>and</strong> philosophical problems, but no matter how <strong>the</strong>y come out, <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

answers won't have <strong>the</strong> impact that some have feared. (This will be a topic <strong>of</strong><br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion in chapter 16.)<br />

The tantalizing recursions <strong>and</strong> reflections <strong>of</strong> evolutionary explanation are<br />

reason enough for philosophers to pay close attention to <strong>the</strong> units-<strong>of</strong>-selection<br />

controversy, but ano<strong>the</strong>r reason it has attracted so much attention is surely<br />

<strong>the</strong> reflection with which we began this section: people feel threatened by <strong>the</strong><br />

gene's-eye perspective for <strong>the</strong> same reason <strong>the</strong>y felt threatened by Charles<br />

Wilson's allegiance to General Motors. People want to be in charge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

own destinies; <strong>the</strong>y take <strong>the</strong>mselves to be both <strong>the</strong> deciders

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!