21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

224 BIOLOGY IS ENGINEERING Stuart Kauffman as MetaEngineer 225<br />

a principle that governs human engineering. Pyramids are always built from<br />

<strong>the</strong> bottom up, <strong>of</strong> course, but <strong>the</strong> organization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> building process, since<br />

<strong>the</strong> days <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pharaohs, has been top-down, under <strong>the</strong> control <strong>of</strong> a single<br />

autocrat who had a clear <strong>and</strong> literally comm<strong>and</strong>ing vision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole, but<br />

probably was a bit vague about how <strong>the</strong> local details would be accomplished.<br />

"Global" direction from on high puts in motion a hierarchical cascade <strong>of</strong><br />

"local" projects. This is such a common feature <strong>of</strong> large-scale human projects<br />

that we have a hard time imagining alternatives (Papert 1993, Dennett<br />

1993a). Since we don't recognize <strong>the</strong> principle Kauffman discerns as one that<br />

is familiar from human engineering, we are not apt to see it as a principle <strong>of</strong><br />

engineering at all, but I suggest that it is. Reformulated slightly, we could put<br />

it as follows. Until you manage to evolve communicating organisms that can<br />

form large engineering organizations, you are bound by <strong>the</strong> following<br />

Preliminary Design Principle: all global order must be generated by local<br />

rules. So all <strong>the</strong> early products <strong>of</strong> design, up to <strong>the</strong> creation <strong>of</strong> something with<br />

some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> organizational talents <strong>of</strong> Homo sapiens, must obey whatever<br />

constraints follow from <strong>the</strong> "management decision" that all order must be<br />

accomplished by local rules. Any "attempts" to create living forms that<br />

violate this precept will end in immediate failure—or, more accurately, will<br />

not even get started sufficiently to be discernible as attempts.<br />

If no bell rings, as I have said, to mark <strong>the</strong> moment when <strong>the</strong> R-<strong>and</strong>-D<br />

process ends <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> life <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> "finished product" begins, it should at least<br />

sometimes be hard to tell whe<strong>the</strong>r a design principle in question is a principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> engineering or <strong>of</strong> meta-engineering. A case in point is Kauffman's (1993,<br />

pp. 75ff.) proposed rederivation <strong>of</strong> "von Baer's laws" <strong>of</strong> embryology. One <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> most striking patterns in <strong>the</strong> embryos <strong>of</strong> animals is <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>y all<br />

start out so much <strong>the</strong> same.<br />

Thus early fish, frog, chick <strong>and</strong> human embryos are remarkably similar __<br />

The familiar explanation for <strong>the</strong>se laws is that mutants [I think he means<br />

"mutations"] affecting early ontogeny are more disruptive than mutants<br />

affecting late ontogeny. Thus mutants altering early development are less<br />

likely to accumulate, <strong>and</strong> early embryos remain more similar from one<br />

order <strong>of</strong> organisms to ano<strong>the</strong>r than do late embryos. Is this plausible argument<br />

actually so plausible? [Kauffman 1993, p. 75]<br />

The traditional Darwinian, on Kauffman's reading, places <strong>the</strong> responsibility<br />

for von Baer's laws in a "special mechanism," built right into organisms.<br />

Why don't we see many finished products with strikingly different early<br />

embryos? Well, since change-orders that affect early parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> process tend<br />

to be more disastrous in <strong>the</strong>ir effect on <strong>the</strong> finished product than changeorders<br />

that affect later parts <strong>of</strong> die process, Mo<strong>the</strong>r Nature has de-<br />

signed a special developmental mechanism to protect against such experimentation.<br />

(This would be analogous to IBM's forbidding its computer<br />

scientists to investigate alternative architectures for its CPU or centralprocessing-unit<br />

chip—designed resistance to change.)<br />

And what is Kauffman's contrasting explanation? It starts with <strong>the</strong> same<br />

point <strong>and</strong> takes it in a ra<strong>the</strong>r different direction:<br />

... a locking-in <strong>of</strong> early development, <strong>and</strong> hence von Baer's laws, do not<br />

represent a special mechanism <strong>of</strong> developmental canalization, <strong>the</strong> usual<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> which is a buffering <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenotype against genetic alteration ___<br />

Instead, locking-in <strong>of</strong> early development is a direct reflection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact<br />

that <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> ways to improve organisms by altering early ontogeny<br />

has dwindled faster than <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> ways to improve by altering late<br />

development. [Kauffman 1993, p. 77. See also Wimsatt 1986.]<br />

Think <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue from <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> human engineering for a<br />

moment. Why is it that <strong>the</strong> foundations <strong>of</strong> churches are more alike than <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

upper stories? Well, says <strong>the</strong> traditional Darwinian, <strong>the</strong>y have to be built first,<br />

<strong>and</strong> any wise contractor will tell you that if you must tinker with design<br />

elements, work on <strong>the</strong> steeple ornament first, or <strong>the</strong> windows. You are less<br />

apt to have a disastrous crash than if you try to come up with a new way <strong>of</strong><br />

preparing <strong>the</strong> foundation. So it is not so surprising that churches all start out<br />

looking more or less alike, with <strong>the</strong> big differences emerging in <strong>the</strong> later<br />

elaborations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> building process. Actually, says Kauffman, <strong>the</strong>re really<br />

just aren't as many different possible solutions to <strong>the</strong> foundation problem as<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are to later building problems. Even stupid contractors who butted <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

heads against this fact for eons would not come up with a wide variety <strong>of</strong><br />

foundation designs. This difference <strong>of</strong> emphasis may look small, but it has<br />

some important implications. Kauffman says we don't need to look for a<br />

canalization mechanism to explain this fact; it will take care <strong>of</strong> itself. But<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is also an underlying agreement between Kauffman <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> tradition he<br />

wants to supplant: <strong>the</strong>re are only so many good ways <strong>of</strong> building things,<br />

given <strong>the</strong> starting constraints, <strong>and</strong> evolution finds <strong>the</strong>m again <strong>and</strong> again.<br />

It is <strong>the</strong> non-optionality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se "choices" that Kauffman wants to stress,<br />

<strong>and</strong> so he <strong>and</strong> his colleague Brian Goodwin (e.g., 1986) are particularly eager<br />

to discredit <strong>the</strong> powerful image, first made popular by <strong>the</strong> great French<br />

biologists Jacques Monod <strong>and</strong> Francois Jacob, <strong>of</strong> Mo<strong>the</strong>r Nature as a<br />

"tinker," engaging in <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> tinkering <strong>the</strong> French call bricolage. The term<br />

was first made salient by <strong>the</strong> anthropologist Claude Levi-Strauss (1966). A<br />

tinker or bricoleur is an opportunistic maker <strong>of</strong> gadgets, a "sat-isficer"<br />

(Simon 1957) who is always ready to settle for mediocrity if it is cheap<br />

enough. A tinker is not a deep thinker. The two elements <strong>of</strong> classical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!