21.03.2015 Views

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

Darwin's Dangerous Idea - Evolution and the Meaning of Life

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

488 ON THE ORIGIN OF MORALITY<br />

factors from cultural commonalities, <strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> same reason. But, although<br />

Wilson has sometimes noted this problem, at o<strong>the</strong>r times he forgets:<br />

The similarities between <strong>the</strong> early civilizations <strong>of</strong> Egypt, Mesopotamia,<br />

India, China, Mexico, <strong>and</strong> Central <strong>and</strong> South America in <strong>the</strong>se major features<br />

are remarkably close. They cannot be explained away as <strong>the</strong> products<br />

<strong>of</strong> chance or cultural cross-fertilization. [Wilson 1978, p. 89]<br />

We need to look at each remarkable similarity in turn, to see if any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m<br />

needs a genetic explanation, for, in addition to cultural cross-fertilization<br />

(cultural descent) <strong>and</strong> chance, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> reinvention. There<br />

may be specific genetic factors operating in many or all <strong>the</strong>se similarities,<br />

but, as Darwin stressed, <strong>the</strong> best evidence will always be idiosyncrasies—<br />

quirky homologies—<strong>and</strong> no-longer-rational survivals. The most compelling<br />

cases <strong>of</strong> this sort are currently being uncovered in <strong>the</strong> marriage <strong>of</strong> sociobiology<br />

<strong>and</strong> cognitive psychology recently going by <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> evolutionary<br />

psychology (Barkow, Cosmides, <strong>and</strong> Tooby 1992 ). Highlighting a single case<br />

will provide a useful contrast between good <strong>and</strong> bad uses <strong>of</strong> Darwinian<br />

thinking in <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> human nature, <strong>and</strong> clarify <strong>the</strong> position on rationality<br />

(or just nonstupidity) just presented.<br />

How logical are we human beings? In some regards very logical, it seems,<br />

<strong>and</strong> in o<strong>the</strong>rs embarrassingly weak. In 1969, <strong>the</strong> psychologist Peter Wason<br />

devised a simple test that bright people—college students, for instance—do<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r badly on. You may try it yourself. Here are four cards, some letterside-up,<br />

<strong>and</strong> some number-side-up. Each card has a numeral on one side <strong>and</strong><br />

a letter on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r:<br />

Your task is to see whe<strong>the</strong>r in this case <strong>the</strong> following rule has any exceptions:<br />

If a card has a "D" on one side, it has a "3" on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side. Now, which<br />

cards do you need to turn over in order to discover if this is true? Sad to say,<br />

fewer than half <strong>of</strong> students in most such experiments get <strong>the</strong> right answer.<br />

Did you? The correct answer is much more obvious if we shift <strong>the</strong> content<br />

(but not <strong>the</strong> structure) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem very slightly. You are <strong>the</strong> bouncer in a<br />

bar, <strong>and</strong> your job depends on not letting any underage (under twenty-one)<br />

customers drink beer. The cards have information about age on one side, <strong>and</strong><br />

what <strong>the</strong> patron is drinking on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. Which cards do you need to turn<br />

over?<br />

Sociobiology: Good <strong>and</strong> Bad Good <strong>and</strong> Evil 489<br />

The first <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> last, obviously, <strong>the</strong> same as in <strong>the</strong> first problem. Why is one<br />

setting so much easier than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r? Perhaps, you may think, it is <strong>the</strong><br />

abstractness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first, <strong>the</strong> concreteness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second, or <strong>the</strong> familiarity <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> second, or <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> second involves a conventional rule, not a<br />

regularity <strong>of</strong> nature. Literally hundreds <strong>of</strong> Wason card-sorting tests have been<br />

administered to subjects, in hundreds <strong>of</strong> variations, testing <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. The performance <strong>of</strong> subjects on <strong>the</strong> tests varies widely,<br />

depending on <strong>the</strong> details <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular test <strong>and</strong> its circumstances, but a<br />

survey <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> results leaves no doubt at all that <strong>the</strong>re are settings that are hard<br />

for almost all groups <strong>of</strong> subjects, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs that are easy for <strong>the</strong> same<br />

subjects. But a riddle remained, reminiscent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> riddle <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two black<br />

boxes: what exactly was it about <strong>the</strong> hard cases that made <strong>the</strong>m hard—or (a<br />

better question) what was it about <strong>the</strong> easy cases that made <strong>the</strong>m easy?<br />

Cosmides <strong>and</strong> Tooby (e.g., Barkow, Cosmides, <strong>and</strong> Tooby 1992, ch. 2 ) came<br />

up with an evolutionary hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, <strong>and</strong> it is hard to imagine this particular<br />

idea occurring to anyone who wasn't acutely aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibilities <strong>of</strong><br />

Darwinian thinking: <strong>the</strong> easy cases are all cases that are readily interpreted as<br />

tasks <strong>of</strong> patrolling a social contract, or, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, cheater detection.<br />

Cosmides <strong>and</strong> Tooby seem to have uncovered a fossil <strong>of</strong> our Nietzschean<br />

past! Framing <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is not yet proving it, <strong>of</strong> course, but one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

important virtues <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is that it is eminently testable, <strong>and</strong> has<br />

so far stood up very well to a wide variety <strong>of</strong> attempts to refute it. Suppose it<br />

is true; would it show that we can reason only about <strong>the</strong> things Mo<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Nature wired us to reason about? Obviously not; it just shows why it is easier<br />

(more "natural") for us to reason about some topics than o<strong>the</strong>rs. We have<br />

devised cultural artifacts (systems <strong>of</strong> formal logic, statistics, decision <strong>the</strong>ory,<br />

<strong>and</strong> so forth, taught in college courses) that exp<strong>and</strong> our reasoning powers<br />

many fold. Even <strong>the</strong> experts <strong>of</strong>ten neglect <strong>the</strong>se specialized techniques,<br />

however, <strong>and</strong> fall back on good old seat-<strong>of</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-pants reasoning, sometimes<br />

with embarrassing results, as <strong>the</strong> Wason test shows. Independently <strong>of</strong> any<br />

Darwinian hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, we know that, except when people are particularly<br />

self-conscious about using <strong>the</strong>se heavy-duty reasoning techniques, <strong>the</strong>y tend<br />

to fall into cognitive illusions. Why are we susceptible to <strong>the</strong>se illusions? The<br />

evolutionary psychologist says: For <strong>the</strong> same reason we are susceptible to<br />

optical illusions <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sensory illusions—we're built that way. Mo<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Nature designed us to solve a certain set <strong>of</strong> problems posed by <strong>the</strong><br />

environments in which we evolved, <strong>and</strong> whenever a cut-rate solution<br />

emerged—a bargain that would solve <strong>the</strong> most pressing problems pretty well,<br />

even if it lacked generality—it tended to get installed.<br />

Cosmides <strong>and</strong> Tooby call <strong>the</strong>se modules "Darwinian algorithms"; <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

mechanisms just like <strong>the</strong> two-bitser, only fancier. We obviously don't get by<br />

with just one such reasoning mechanism. Cosmides <strong>and</strong> Tooby have been<br />

ga<strong>the</strong>ring evidence for o<strong>the</strong>r special-purpose algorithms, useful in thinking

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!