11.07.2015 Views

wise use of mires and peatlands - Peatland Ecology Research Group

wise use of mires and peatlands - Peatland Ecology Research Group

wise use of mires and peatlands - Peatland Ecology Research Group

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

116 VALUES AND CONFLICTS: WHERE DIFFERENT VALUES MEET<strong>of</strong> justice are those that would be agreed to byfree <strong>and</strong> rational persons, placed in the “originalposition” behind a veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance: not knowingtheir place in society; their class, race, or sex;their abilities, intelligence, or strengths; or eventheir conception <strong>of</strong> good. In contrast to theUniversal Declaration on Human Rights, that islargely founded on a western metaphysicalconcept <strong>of</strong> rights, Rawls’ principles follow theKantian approach <strong>of</strong> rationality <strong>and</strong>universalisation (the “categorical imperative”):Act only on a rule that you wish to see generallyfollowed by everyone. Accordingly, he derivestwo principles <strong>of</strong> justice to regulate thedistribution <strong>of</strong> liberties, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economicgoods.47Basic liberties include: political liberty (the rightto vote <strong>and</strong> to be eligible for public <strong>of</strong>fice) togetherwith freedom <strong>of</strong> speech <strong>and</strong> assembly; liberty <strong>of</strong>conscience <strong>and</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> thought; freedom <strong>of</strong>the person along with the right to hold (personal)property; <strong>and</strong> freedom from arbitrary arrest <strong>and</strong>seizure as defined by the concept <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong>law (Rawls 1971).48To deal with intergenerational relations, Rawlsintroduced the concept <strong>of</strong> “just savings”, implyingwhat is reasonable for members <strong>of</strong> succeedinggenerations to expect from one another bybalancing how much they would be willing to savefor their immediate descendants against what theywould feel entitled to claim <strong>of</strong> their immediatepredecessors.49This section draws substantially on the ideas <strong>of</strong>Hampicke (2000).50World Commission on Environment <strong>and</strong>Development 1987.51Howarth 2000.52Some technological optimists, for example,expect that the science <strong>of</strong> ecology will eventuallyprovide sufficient underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> ecologicalprocesses <strong>and</strong> relationships to enable an effectivecontrol <strong>of</strong> ecosystems <strong>and</strong> natural resources. Thisbelief disregards the fundamental scientificlimitations to ecological knowledge: theenormous complexity <strong>of</strong> ecosystems, theunpredictability <strong>of</strong> their dynamics due to chaos<strong>and</strong> contingency, their uniqueness which precludesfar-reaching generalisations, <strong>and</strong> the limitedpossibilities <strong>of</strong> quantifying their qualities (Gorke1999).53Hampicke 2000.54Cf. Alex<strong>and</strong>er Solzhenitsyn (1968): “Happinessis a mirage – as for the so-called “happiness <strong>of</strong>future generations” it is even more <strong>of</strong> a mirage.Who knows anything about it? Who has spokenwith these future generations? Who knows whichidols they will worship? Ideas <strong>of</strong> what happinessis have changed too much through the ages. Noone should have the effrontery to try <strong>and</strong> plan itin advance.”55Barry 1977.56I.e. the material life support functions.57Dasgupta, 1995.58“Almost every article, paper or book onsustainability bemoans the fact that the conceptis broad <strong>and</strong> lacks a broad consensus; this is usuallyfollowed by the authors’ own preferred definitionswhich in turn add to the lack <strong>of</strong> consensus!” (Bell& Morse 1999).59Neumayer 1999.60The distinction between weak <strong>and</strong> strongsustainability is similar to that <strong>of</strong> the distinctionbetween the “sustainability <strong>of</strong> the means to anend” <strong>and</strong> the “sustainability <strong>of</strong> the end” (Bell &Morse 1999). E.g. “sustainable peatl<strong>and</strong> forestry”generally refers to the sustainability <strong>of</strong> forestryon that spot, not to the sustainability <strong>of</strong> peatl<strong>and</strong>,as the peat may eventually disappear as a result<strong>of</strong> drainage (cf. Päiväinen 1997, 2000).61See also §5.6.5 (2) below.62I.e. the maximisation <strong>of</strong> the well-being <strong>of</strong> allpresent <strong>and</strong> future humankind.63This is also expressed in the Ramsar definition <strong>of</strong>sustainable utilisation: “the greatest continuousbenefit to present generations while maintainingits potential to meet the needs <strong>and</strong> aspirations <strong>of</strong>future generations”.64Cf. Dasgupta 1995.65See §5.6.5 (2) below. If, for example, society in100 years will need a specific sum <strong>of</strong> money tomitigate the consequences <strong>of</strong> climatic change, amuch lower sum can be invested today <strong>and</strong> thissum will increase to its final size 100 years fromnow, according to the laws <strong>of</strong> compound interest.66Pigou 1978.67Hampicke 2000.68Hampicke 2000.69This does not exclude the possibility that advancestowards solving these problems or substitutingthe concrete services <strong>and</strong> resources might be madeat some time in the future.70Ott 2000.71Rehmann-Sutter 1998.72Sober 1985.73Those who consider their loss acceptable shouldindicate how they are substitutable. There canalso be discussion regarding whether a particularfunction is essential or substitutable.74In considering which part <strong>of</strong> biodiversity is vital,it can be asked from the anthropocentric point<strong>of</strong> view on which this document is based, whetherwe have to preserve all <strong>mires</strong>, all mire species<strong>and</strong> all peat? To what extent is their maintenancenecessary for maximising human happiness (orminimising human suffering)? To what extent istheir abundance redundant <strong>and</strong> <strong>use</strong>less?The probability <strong>of</strong> an unknown property <strong>of</strong> aspecies being directly <strong>use</strong>ful for humankind infuture is low, beca<strong>use</strong> it is the product <strong>of</strong> two lowprobabilities: (i) that the species indeed is <strong>use</strong>ful,<strong>and</strong> (ii) that its <strong>use</strong> will be discovered (Norton1987). In a world with tens <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> species,the loss <strong>of</strong> a currently <strong>use</strong>less species maytherefore be <strong>of</strong> negligible importance. It is,furthermore, irrational to defer some real <strong>and</strong>known benefit in favour <strong>of</strong> a theoreticallypossible but still unknown <strong>use</strong> <strong>of</strong> certain species(“a bird in the h<strong>and</strong> is worth two in the bush”).Contrary to what ecologists thought in the 1970s,species diversity is no longer regarded as a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!