03.04.2013 Views

THE STORY OF PHILOSOPHY2 The Lives and Opinions

THE STORY OF PHILOSOPHY2 The Lives and Opinions

THE STORY OF PHILOSOPHY2 The Lives and Opinions

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

PLATO 17<br />

This, of course, is the doctrine which our own day more or less correctly<br />

associates with the name of Nietzsche. "Verily I laughed many a<br />

time over the weaklings who thought themselves good because they had<br />

lame paws." 11 Stirner expressed the idea briefly when he said that "a<br />

h<strong>and</strong>ful of might is better than a bagful of right." Perhaps nowhere in<br />

the history of philosophy is the doctrine better formulated than by Plato<br />

himself in another dialogue, Gorgias, (483 f), where the Sophist Gallicles<br />

denounces morality as an invention of the weak to neutralize the strength<br />

of the strong.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y distribute praise <strong>and</strong> censure with a view to their own interests;<br />

they say that dishonesty is shameful <strong>and</strong> unjust meaning by dishonesty the<br />

desire to have more than their neighbors; for knowing their own inferiority,<br />

they would be only too glad to have equality. . . . But if there were a man<br />

who had sufficient force (enter the Superman), he would shake off <strong>and</strong><br />

break through <strong>and</strong> escape from all this; he would trample under foot all our<br />

formulas <strong>and</strong> spells <strong>and</strong> charms, <strong>and</strong> all our laws, that sin against nature.<br />

... He who would truly live ought to allow his desires to wax to the utter-<br />

most; but when they have grown to their greatest he should have courage<br />

<strong>and</strong> intelligence to minister to them, <strong>and</strong> to satisfy all his longings. And this<br />

I affirm to be natural justice <strong>and</strong> nobility. But the many cannot do this;<br />

<strong>and</strong> therefore they blame such persons, because they are ashamed of their<br />

own inability, which they desire to conceal; <strong>and</strong> hence they call intemperance<br />

base. . . . <strong>The</strong>y enslave the nobler natures, <strong>and</strong> they praise justice<br />

only because they are cowards.<br />

This justice is a morality not for men but for foot-men (oude gar <strong>and</strong>ros<br />

all' <strong>and</strong>rapodou tinos) it is a ; slave-morality, not a hero-morality; the<br />

real virtues of a man are courage (<strong>and</strong>reia) <strong>and</strong> 12<br />

.<br />

intelligence (phronesis]<br />

Perhaps this hard "immoralism" reflects the development of imperialism<br />

in the foreign policy of Athens, <strong>and</strong> its ruthless treatment of weaker<br />

states. 13 "Your empire," said Pericles in the oration which Thucydides<br />

invents for him, "is based on your own strength rather than the good will<br />

of your subjects." And the same historian reports the Athenian envoys<br />

coercing Melos into joining Athens in the war against Sparta: "You<br />

know as well as we do that right, as the world goes, is only in question<br />

for equals in power; the strong do what they can, <strong>and</strong> the weak suffer<br />

what they must." 14 We have here the fundamental problem of ethics,<br />

the crux of the theory of moral conduct. What is justice? shall we seek<br />

righteousness, or shall we seek power? is it better to be good,<br />

or to be<br />

strong?<br />

How does Socrates i. e., Plato meet the challenge of this theory? At<br />

u Thus Spake Zarathustra, New York, 1906, p. 166.<br />

^Gorgias 491; cf. Machiavelli's definition of virtb as intellect plus force.<br />

""Barker, p. 73.<br />

u Historv of the Peloponnesian War, v. 105.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!