13.05.2013 Views

historical and political thought in the seventeenth - RePub - Erasmus ...

historical and political thought in the seventeenth - RePub - Erasmus ...

historical and political thought in the seventeenth - RePub - Erasmus ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Chapter 8. The science of politics. The Institutiones politicae<br />

sociability is completely absent. 62 Instead, Boxhorn provides his readers with<br />

a gloomy description of <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong> of <strong>political</strong> society <strong>and</strong> of man’s nature<br />

that strongly suggests that it was not ‘special to man’ to live with his fellow<br />

men, but that he was forced to do so by <strong>the</strong> circumstances he found himself<br />

<strong>in</strong>. 63 This was a l<strong>in</strong>e of <strong>thought</strong> that Arnisaeus, one of <strong>the</strong> found<strong>in</strong>g fa<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

of <strong>the</strong> politica genre, had associated with Plato, Machiavelli, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Spanish<br />

Jesuit Juan de Mariana (1536-1624), 64 <strong>and</strong> for which Hobbes, <strong>the</strong> bro<strong>the</strong>rs De<br />

la Court, <strong>and</strong> Sp<strong>in</strong>oza would become notorious, that is, a l<strong>in</strong>e of <strong>thought</strong> that<br />

took man’s unsociability as its po<strong>in</strong>t of departure <strong>and</strong> that grounded <strong>the</strong> foundation<br />

<strong>and</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>political</strong> society on a negative anthropology of fear,<br />

ambition, <strong>and</strong> self-<strong>in</strong>terest. 65<br />

62 That is, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sections attributed to Boxhorn. It can be found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> commentaries of George<br />

Hornius. See Boxhorn, Institutiones politicae, II.10, p. 359 [365].<br />

63 I <strong>the</strong>refore disagree with Ernst Kossmann’s judgement that Boxhorn, whom Kossmann classified<br />

as an erudite but superficial scholar, represented <strong>the</strong> merry side of <strong>the</strong> Baroque age, who followed<br />

<strong>the</strong> latest popular trends, <strong>and</strong> who, unlike <strong>the</strong> bro<strong>the</strong>rs De la Court, could f<strong>in</strong>d amusement <strong>in</strong> men’s<br />

wicked ways. On account of <strong>the</strong>se arguments, Kossmann concluded that scholars like Boxhorn had felt<br />

no need to develop methods by which better forms of social <strong>and</strong> <strong>political</strong> behaviour could be achieved.<br />

As this chapter will show, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of Boxhorn <strong>the</strong> very opposite is true. Kossmann, “Enkele laatzeventiende-eeuwse<br />

Nederl<strong>and</strong>se geschriften over Raison d’Etat”, pp. 103-6.<br />

64 Henn<strong>in</strong>g Arnisaeus, Doctr<strong>in</strong>a politica (Lowijs Elzevier; Amsterdam, 1651), I.2, p. 46. ‘Plato quidem,<br />

3. de ll. & ferè Machiav. l. 1. disc. ad 1. Dec. Liv. c. I. Ioh. Marian. l. I. de reg. <strong>in</strong>stit. c. I. hom<strong>in</strong>es putat<br />

primum egestate & necessitate compulsos societatem <strong>in</strong>iisse. Sed Arist. 4. pol. 4. illam sententiam meritò<br />

improbat, quoniam, ut <strong>in</strong> loci illius enarratione dicit Thomas, civitas non est propter ipsum vivere, sed<br />

propter benè vivere.’ For a discussion of Arnisaeus’s own view on <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of society, see Brett,<br />

Changes of State, p. 119.<br />

65 This l<strong>in</strong>e of <strong>thought</strong> has a religious counterpart <strong>in</strong> August<strong>in</strong>e’s negative picture of <strong>the</strong> unavoidable<br />

persistence of human s<strong>in</strong>fulness due to <strong>the</strong> Fall, <strong>and</strong> his subsequent view of politics as ‘<strong>the</strong> means<br />

to achieve m<strong>in</strong>imum disorder’. Janet Coleman, A History of Political Thought, Vol. 1: From Ancient Greece<br />

to Early Christianity (Blackwell Publishers; Oxford/Malden, 2000), pp. 330-37, with quote on p. 333. Tak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

his cue from <strong>the</strong> same Spanish Late-Scholastic tradition by which Boxhorn was <strong>in</strong>fluenced, Samuel<br />

Ru<strong>the</strong>rford (c.1600-1660), writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early 1640s, also po<strong>in</strong>ted out to <strong>the</strong> artificial <strong>and</strong> unnatural<br />

foundation of <strong>political</strong> society. Although he accepted that ‘God hath made man a social creature, <strong>and</strong><br />

one who <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>eth to be governed by men’ (specific reference to Aristotle, Politics, 1252b1-1253a1 [I:2]),<br />

he also argued that ‘if all men be born equally free … <strong>the</strong>re is no reason <strong>in</strong> nature why one should be<br />

k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> lord over ano<strong>the</strong>r; <strong>the</strong>refore … I conceive all jurisdiction of man over man to be as it were<br />

artificial <strong>and</strong> positive, <strong>and</strong> that it <strong>in</strong>ferreth some servitude whereof nature from <strong>the</strong> womb hath freed<br />

us …’ (specific reference to Vázquez, Controversiarum illustrium, I.42.28-29). Samuel Ru<strong>the</strong>rford, Lex,<br />

Rex, or <strong>the</strong> Law <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ce (Spr<strong>in</strong>kle Publications; Harrisonburg, 1982), pp. 1-2. For Ru<strong>the</strong>rford <strong>and</strong><br />

his modification of <strong>the</strong> arguments put forward by <strong>the</strong> Spanish Late-Scholastics, see Robert von Friedeburg,<br />

“Bauste<strong>in</strong>e widerst<strong>and</strong>srechtlicher Argumente <strong>in</strong> der frühen Neuzeit (1523-1668): Konfessionen,<br />

klassische Verfassungsvorbilder, Naturrecht, direkter Befehl Gottes, historische Rechte der Geme<strong>in</strong>wesen”,<br />

<strong>in</strong> Christoph Strohm <strong>and</strong> He<strong>in</strong>rich de Wall (eds.), Konfessionalität und Jurisprudenz <strong>in</strong> der frühen<br />

Neuzeit (Duncker <strong>and</strong> Humblot; Berl<strong>in</strong>, 2009), pp. 130-31, 154-56. In his analysis of Ru<strong>the</strong>rford’s ‘m<strong>in</strong>d’<br />

John Coffey, who classifies Lex, Rex as an <strong>in</strong> some ways ‘deeply Thomistic book’, tries to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

two seem<strong>in</strong>gly opposed ideas of Ru<strong>the</strong>rford by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out to <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction that Ru<strong>the</strong>rford draws<br />

between <strong>political</strong> society be<strong>in</strong>g natural ‘<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> root’ <strong>and</strong> voluntary ‘<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> manner of coalesc<strong>in</strong>g’. John<br />

Coffey, Politics, Religion <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> British Revolutions: The M<strong>in</strong>d of Samuel Ru<strong>the</strong>rford (Cambridge University<br />

Press; Cambridge, 1997), pp. 152, 158-63.<br />

257

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!