13.05.2013 Views

historical and political thought in the seventeenth - RePub - Erasmus ...

historical and political thought in the seventeenth - RePub - Erasmus ...

historical and political thought in the seventeenth - RePub - Erasmus ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

280<br />

Chapter 8. The science of politics. The Institutiones politicae<br />

who belong to that section cannot love <strong>the</strong> form of government. In this particular<br />

case, ‘to love’ (amare) is directly connected to <strong>in</strong>volvement of <strong>the</strong> self<br />

(ego). To this syllogism we can connect Boxhorn’s observation that <strong>the</strong> most<br />

peaceful commonwealths are those <strong>in</strong> which even <strong>the</strong> lower magistrates,<br />

who Boxhorn describes as <strong>the</strong> representatives of <strong>the</strong> people, feel that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are admitted to <strong>the</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istration of <strong>the</strong> commonwealth. Here, once aga<strong>in</strong>,<br />

<strong>the</strong> Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> ancient Rome, after <strong>the</strong> plebs had been given access to<br />

adm<strong>in</strong>istrative offices, serve as <strong>the</strong> prime examples. 164<br />

In l<strong>in</strong>e with this reason<strong>in</strong>g is Boxhorn’s st<strong>and</strong> that, at least <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory, no<br />

<strong>in</strong>habitant of a commonwealth should be barred from obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g an adm<strong>in</strong>istrative<br />

office, ‘for private <strong>in</strong>dividuals should not be denied what is held <strong>in</strong><br />

common’. 165 From this we can conclude that an adm<strong>in</strong>istrative office is common<br />

property, <strong>and</strong> that, at least <strong>in</strong> this case, Boxhorn sees <strong>the</strong> res publica, which<br />

he def<strong>in</strong>es <strong>in</strong> non-Ciceronian terms as a ‘body of many’, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ciceronian<br />

sense of a res populi, <strong>the</strong> collective property of <strong>the</strong> people. 166<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Boxhorn, <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of ‘non-exclusion’ carries four major<br />

benefits. First, it excites <strong>in</strong> people a greater love for <strong>the</strong> commonwealth,<br />

because <strong>the</strong> fact that no one should be excluded from office demonstrates to<br />

<strong>the</strong> people ‘<strong>the</strong> greatness of liberty’ that rests on a system of rul<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

ruled <strong>in</strong> turn. 167 Second, it contributes to <strong>the</strong> concord with<strong>in</strong> a commonwealth,<br />

164 Ibidem, I.3, pp. 22-23. ‘Itaque <strong>in</strong> Regno Optimatum & Populi; <strong>in</strong> Optimatum regim<strong>in</strong>e Populi; <strong>in</strong><br />

Democratia Optimum habenda ratio est; atque <strong>in</strong>dè pacatissimae sunt Respublicae, <strong>in</strong> quibus & m<strong>in</strong>ores<br />

Magistratus curam Reipublicae ad se pert<strong>in</strong>ere sentiunt. In Belgio sanè nullus status exclusum se à<br />

Republica queri potest. Comitia enim constituunt Nobiles & Civitatum delegati, qui posteriores sunt<br />

quasi Optimates è populo, atque <strong>in</strong>dè facillimè consensus vel <strong>in</strong> gravissimis rebus impetratur. Nam<br />

si delegati consentiant <strong>in</strong> Tributa; populus id non potest impedire, quia omnem sui consensus vim <strong>in</strong><br />

eos transfundit. Ita & Respublica Romana turbata mirificè fuit, antequam plebs ad Reipublicae munia<br />

admissa fuisset.’ For Rome, see also ibidem, I.8, p. 105, <strong>and</strong> chapter 7 of this <strong>the</strong>sis.<br />

165 Ibidem, I.8, p. 105. ‘Nemo etiam à Magistratu excludendus, juxta §. 6. quia quod commune omnium<br />

est, s<strong>in</strong>gulis non debet denegari.’ Ibidem, I.8.5, p. 97. ‘Via igitur ad honores munienda est <strong>in</strong>quil<strong>in</strong>is.’<br />

166 If this is true, <strong>the</strong>n one has to be careful of speak<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> state as an abstract entity, separated<br />

<strong>and</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>guishable from its citizens, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> Romans had no such conception of a res publica. See<br />

Wood, Cicero’s Social <strong>and</strong> Political Thought, pp. 124-26. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Aristotle, what def<strong>in</strong>es a citizen is<br />

‘that he shares <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istration of justice, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> offices’. Aristotle, Politics, 1275a1 [III:1], p. 62.<br />

‘Thus’, as Richard Mulgan has expla<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian sense ‘full membership of a city implies<br />

participation, or at least <strong>the</strong> right to participate, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>political</strong> duties of citizenship’. Mulgan, however,<br />

also po<strong>in</strong>ts out that Aristotle’s view on <strong>political</strong> participation was ambivalent; <strong>the</strong> good citizen could<br />

also be good <strong>and</strong> live a virtuous life without fulfill<strong>in</strong>g an office. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, Aristotle had described<br />

his ideal state (books VII-VIII) as a polis <strong>in</strong> which men of equal virtue share <strong>in</strong> rul<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g ruled;<br />

however, if <strong>the</strong>re was someone, or a few people who would exceed <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong> matters of virtue <strong>and</strong><br />

ability, <strong>the</strong>y should rule <strong>in</strong>stead of <strong>the</strong> whole citizen-body. Here we come across Aristotle’s notion of<br />

distributive justice, giv<strong>in</strong>g each man his due, a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple also followed by Cicero. Aristotle, Politics,<br />

1283b1-1284a1 [III:13], p. 81, <strong>and</strong> Richard Mulgan, “Aristotle <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Value of Political Participation”,<br />

<strong>in</strong> Political Theory, Vol. 18, No. 2 (1990), pp. 195-215, esp. pp. 203-8, with quote on p. 206. For a more<br />

elaborate discussion of this topic, see Nieuwstraten, “Why <strong>the</strong> Wealthy should rule”, pp. 126-49.<br />

167 Boxhorn, Institutiones politicae, I.8, p. 105. ‘Accedit quod hoc faciat: I. ad Reip. amorem majorem<br />

<strong>in</strong> omnibus excit<strong>and</strong>um: quippe sic ostenditur & magnitudo libertatis, quae <strong>in</strong> vicissitud<strong>in</strong>e parendi<br />

& imper<strong>and</strong>i consistit, & reprimitur Insolentia Magistratuum.’ Probably because where everyone is

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!