31.10.2014 Views

A history of Greek mathematics - Wilbourhall.org

A history of Greek mathematics - Wilbourhall.org

A history of Greek mathematics - Wilbourhall.org

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

228 SUCCESSORS OF THE GREAT GEOMETERS<br />

straight lines which happens in the case <strong>of</strong> the lines referred<br />

to? Indeed, until the statement in the postulate is clinched<br />

by pro<strong>of</strong>, the facts shown in the case <strong>of</strong> the other lines may<br />

direct our imagination the opposite way. And, though the<br />

controversial arguments against the meeting <strong>of</strong> the straight<br />

lines should contain much that is surprising, is there not all<br />

the more reason why we should expel from our body <strong>of</strong><br />

doctrine this merely plausible and unreasoned (hypothesis) ?<br />

It is clear from this that we must seek a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the present<br />

theorem, and that it is alien to the special character <strong>of</strong><br />

postulates.' l<br />

Much <strong>of</strong> this might have been written by a modern<br />

geometer. Geminus's attempted remedy was to substitute<br />

a definition <strong>of</strong> parallels like that <strong>of</strong> Posidonius, based on the<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> eqvAdistance. An-Nairizi gives the definition as<br />

follows :<br />

'<br />

Parallel straight lines are straight lines situated in<br />

the same plane and such that the distance between them, if<br />

they are produced without limit in both directions at the same<br />

time, is everywhere the same ', to which Geminus adds the<br />

statement that the said distance is<br />

the shortest straight line<br />

that can be drawn between them. Starting from this,<br />

Geminus proved to his own satisfaction the propositions <strong>of</strong><br />

Euclid regarding parallels and finally the parallel-postulate.<br />

He first gave the propositions (1) that the 'distance ' between<br />

the two lines as defined is perpendicular to both, and (2) that,<br />

if a straight line is perpendicular to each <strong>of</strong> two straight lines<br />

and meets both, the two straight lines are parallel, and the<br />

'<br />

distance ' is the intercept on the perpendicular (proved by<br />

reductio ad absurdum). Next come (3) Euclid's propositions<br />

I. 27, 28 that, if two lines are parallel, the alternate angles<br />

made by any transversal are equal, &c. (easily proved by<br />

drawing the two equal ' distances ' through the points <strong>of</strong><br />

intersection with the transversal), and (4) Eucl. I. 29, the converse<br />

<strong>of</strong> I. 28, which is proved lyy reductio ad absurdum, by<br />

means <strong>of</strong> (2) and (3). Geminus still needs Eucl. I. 30, 31<br />

(about parallels) and I. 33, 34 (the first two propositions<br />

relating to parallelograms) for his final pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the postulate,<br />

which is to the following effect.<br />

Let A B, CD be two straight lines met by the straight line<br />

1<br />

Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 192. 5-193. 3.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!