31.10.2014 Views

A history of Greek mathematics - Wilbourhall.org

A history of Greek mathematics - Wilbourhall.org

A history of Greek mathematics - Wilbourhall.org

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

230 SUCCESSORS OF THE GREAT GEOMETERS<br />

What follows is actually that both EQ and AB (<strong>of</strong> EB)<br />

are parallel to LV, and Geminus assumes that EQ, AB<br />

are coincident (in other words, that through a given point<br />

only one parallel can be drawn to a given straight line, an<br />

assumption known as PJayfair's Axiom, though it is actually<br />

stated in Proclus on Eucl. I. 31).<br />

The pro<strong>of</strong> therefore, apparently ingenious as it is, breaks<br />

down. Indeed the method is unsound from the beginning,<br />

since (as Saccheri pointed out), before even the definition <strong>of</strong><br />

parallels by Geminus can be used, it has to be proved that<br />

'<br />

the geometrical locus <strong>of</strong> points equidistant from* a straight<br />

line is a straight line ', and this cannot be proved without a<br />

postulate. But the attempt is interesting as the first which<br />

has come down to us, although there must have. been many<br />

others by geometers earlier than Geminus.<br />

Coming now to the things which follow from the principles<br />

(rd fxtTa ras dp\ds), we gather from Proclus that Geminus<br />

carefully discussed such generalities as the nature <strong>of</strong> elements,<br />

the different views which had been held <strong>of</strong> the distinction<br />

between theorems and problems, the nature and significance<br />

<strong>of</strong> Siopio-jioL (conditions and limits <strong>of</strong> possibility), the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> ( porism in the sense in which Euclid used the word in his<br />

'<br />

Porisms as distinct from its other meaning <strong>of</strong> corollary ' ', the<br />

different sorts <strong>of</strong> problems and theorems, the two varieties <strong>of</strong><br />

converses (complete and partial), topical or locus-theorems,<br />

with the classification <strong>of</strong> loci. He discussed also philosophical<br />

questions, e.g. the question whether a line is made up <strong>of</strong><br />

indivisible parts (e£ djxepcov), which came up in connexion<br />

with Eucl. I. 10 (the bisection <strong>of</strong> a straight line).<br />

The book was evidently not less exhaustive as regards<br />

higher geometry. Not only did Geminus mention the spiric<br />

curves, conchoids and cissoids in his classification <strong>of</strong> curves ;<br />

he showed how they were obtained, and gave pro<strong>of</strong>s, presumably<br />

<strong>of</strong> their principal properties. Similarly he gave the<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> that there are three homoeomeric or uniform lines or<br />

curves, the straight line, the circle and the cylindrical helix.<br />

The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> ' uniformity ' (the property that any portion <strong>of</strong><br />

the line or curve will coincide with any other portion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

same length) was preceded by a pro<strong>of</strong> that, if two straight<br />

lines be drawn from any point to meet a uniform line or curve

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!