30.10.2012 Views

Public Management and Administration - Owen E.hughes

Public Management and Administration - Owen E.hughes

Public Management and Administration - Owen E.hughes

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

126 <strong>Public</strong> <strong>Management</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Administration</strong><br />

it fails to be disproved. As an example of the difference, consider the traffic<br />

problem mentioned earlier. An inductive approach to traffic congestion would<br />

involve gathering data about traffic conditions, making sense of it <strong>and</strong> making<br />

conclusions from the data. A deductive or public choice approach would<br />

assume there was a good being maximized by people; in this case probably<br />

time, so predictions could be made about what the behaviour of people might<br />

be in trying to minimize the time taken in traffic. Instead of trying to derive<br />

explanations of behaviour, that is taken as assumed.<br />

Undemocratic<br />

Following the rational model by analysis of the facts, <strong>and</strong> deriving the best<br />

possible outcome, could be undemocratic unless the solution happened to agree<br />

with what the target audience or the wider political system wanted. This would<br />

only occur by chance. Denhardt argues that policy analysts typically apply<br />

technical solutions to the solution of immediate problems <strong>and</strong> ‘under such circumstances,<br />

technical concerns would displace political <strong>and</strong> ethical concerns<br />

as the basis for public decision making, thereby transforming normative issues<br />

into technical problems’ (1981, p. 631). Even a small-scale issue such as the<br />

location of a road can rarely be decided technically as there are people involved<br />

who will not accept a technical solution. Politics, as required by a democracy,<br />

may intervene unless a technical answer is imposed, which would often be<br />

undemocratic. As deLeon notes (1997, p. 100), ‘the analytic priesthood is<br />

doing little to discourage the ebbing of … faith in government <strong>and</strong>, by extension,<br />

the democratic system, as it carries out its personal preferences, in procedure<br />

if not in specific programs’.<br />

Responses to criticism<br />

Criticisms have been made about policy analysis for some years. In a defence<br />

of the approach, Nagel (1990, p. 429) argued that policy analysis can incorporate<br />

other values than those for which it is criticized <strong>and</strong> move away from those<br />

things criticized earlier. He refers to the traditional goals under the ‘three Es’<br />

of effectiveness, efficiency, <strong>and</strong> equity. According to him, effectiveness refers<br />

to the benefits achieved by alternative public policies; efficiency refers to keeping<br />

costs down in achieving benefits, as measured by benefits minus costs or a<br />

maximum level of costs across persons, groups, or places. He says that these<br />

should also be balanced with the ‘three Ps’ as high-level goals, meaning public<br />

participation, predictability, <strong>and</strong> procedural due process. <strong>Public</strong> participation<br />

refers to decision-making by the target group, the general public or other relevant<br />

interest groups; predictability refers to making decisions so that a similar<br />

decision would be arrived at by others following the same criteria, while procedural<br />

due process, or procedural fairness, means those who have been

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!