05.04.2013 Views

history of mathematics - National STEM Centre

history of mathematics - National STEM Centre

history of mathematics - National STEM Centre

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

7 Constructing algebraic solutions<br />

On the nature <strong>of</strong> curves<br />

In La Geometric, Descartes pushed back some <strong>of</strong> the frontiers which had restricted<br />

mathematicians. You have already seen that the introduction <strong>of</strong> the unit and - more<br />

or less related to this - the relaxing <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> homogeneity, enabled a fruitful<br />

interaction between geometry and algebra to take place. This cleared the way for a<br />

generally applicable method for solving geometrical construction problems.<br />

However, yet another step was needed. What use is the method <strong>of</strong> analysis if you<br />

cannot then construct the solution? What about equations <strong>of</strong> third and higher<br />

degree? In general, the solutions <strong>of</strong> these equations cannot be constructed with a<br />

pair <strong>of</strong> compasses and a straight edge. But how can you construct them? Can you<br />

use other curves and circles?<br />

Here, too, Descartes proved himself to be original and creative. Before he supported<br />

carrying out constructions with curves other than straight lines and circles, he<br />

discusses the nature <strong>of</strong> geometrical curves in Book II.<br />

The book begins as follows.<br />

Geometry<br />

Book II<br />

On the Nature <strong>of</strong> Curved Lines<br />

21 The ancients were familiar with the fact that the problems <strong>of</strong><br />

geometry may be divided into three classes, namely, plane, solid, and<br />

linear problems. This is equivalent to saying that some problems require<br />

only circles and straight lines for their construction, while others require a<br />

conic section and still others require more complex curves. I am surprised,<br />

however, that they did not go further, and distinguish between different<br />

degrees <strong>of</strong> these more complex curves, nor do I see why they called the<br />

latter mechanical rather than geometrical.<br />

22 If we say that they are called mechanical because some sort <strong>of</strong><br />

instrument has to be used to describe them, then we must, to be<br />

consistent, reject circles and straight lines, since these cannot be<br />

described on paper without the use <strong>of</strong> compasses and a ruler, which may<br />

also be termed instruments. It is not because other instruments, being<br />

more complicated than the ruler and compasses, are therefore less<br />

accurate, for if this were so they would have to be excluded from<br />

mechanics, in which the accuracy <strong>of</strong> construction is even more important<br />

than in geometry. In the latter, the exactness <strong>of</strong> reasoning alone is sought,<br />

and this can surely be as thorough with reference to such lines as to<br />

simpler ones. I cannot believe, either, that it was because they did not<br />

wish to make more than two postulates, namely (1) a straight line can be<br />

drawn through any two points, and (2) about a given centre a circle can be<br />

described passing through a given point. In their treatment <strong>of</strong> the conic<br />

sections they did not hesitate to introduce the assumption that any given<br />

cone can be cut by a given plane. Now to treat all the curves which I mean<br />

to introduce here, only one additional assumption is necessary, namely,<br />

two or more lines can be moved, one upon the other, determining by their<br />

intersection other curves. This seems to me in no way more difficult.<br />

93

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!