05.01.2013 Views

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

108 Chapter 6. Algebraic insolubility <strong>of</strong> the quintic<br />

ensured ABEL that any expression which he was to encounter in the hierarchy <strong>of</strong> a<br />

solvable equation, would depend rationally on the roots <strong>of</strong> the given equation.<br />

6.4 ABEL and the theory <strong>of</strong> permutations: the<br />

CAUCHY-RUFFINI theorem revisited<br />

<strong>The</strong> second preliminary pillar <strong>of</strong> ABEL’S impossibility pro<strong>of</strong> was made up <strong>of</strong> his stud-<br />

ies <strong>of</strong> permutations and his pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the CAUCHY-RUFFINI theorem describing the<br />

possible numbers <strong>of</strong> values <strong>of</strong> rational functions under permutations <strong>of</strong> their argu-<br />

ments. Prior to giving his pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> this central result, ABEL summarized much <strong>of</strong> what<br />

CAUCHY had done in his 1815-paper, 27 and in doing so ABEL took over CAUCHY’S<br />

notation and much <strong>of</strong> his terminology. But while CAUCHY had begun the process <strong>of</strong><br />

liberating the substitutions from the expressions on which they acted, ABEL contin-<br />

ued the tradition <strong>of</strong> LAGRANGE. Although he occasionally spoke <strong>of</strong> the “substitution”<br />

[Vervandlung] as an independent object, all his deductions concerned their actions on<br />

expressions.<br />

“Now let<br />

A1<br />

A2<br />

� �<br />

αβγδ . . .<br />

v<br />

abcd . . .<br />

be the value, which an arbitrary function v takes, when therein xa, xb, xc, xd etc. are<br />

inserted instead <strong>of</strong> xα, xβ, xγ, xδ etc.; then it is clear that, when by A1, A2 . . . Aµ one<br />

denotes the different forms which 1, 2, 3, 4 . . . n can possibly take by interchanges<br />

<strong>of</strong> the exponents 1, 2, 3 . . . n, the different values <strong>of</strong> v can be expressed as<br />

� � � � � � � �<br />

A1 A1 A1 A1<br />

v , v , v . . . v .” 28<br />

A3<br />

With this notation, ABEL proved LAGRANGE’S theorem that the number <strong>of</strong> differ-<br />

ent values <strong>of</strong> the function v would be a divisor <strong>of</strong> n!. Next, he introduced the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> recurring substitutions [wiederkehrende Verwandlungen] <strong>of</strong> order p, thereby re-<br />

placing the word degree chosen by CAUCHY. In the 1840s, CAUCHY was to take up<br />

ABEL’S terminology on this point. 29 Through a counting argument based on what<br />

27 (A.-L. Cauchy, 1815a).<br />

28 “Nun sei<br />

� �<br />

αβγδ . . .<br />

v<br />

abcd . . .<br />

der Werth, welchen eine beliebige Function v bekommt, wenn man darin xa, x b, xc, x d etc. statt<br />

xα, x β, xγ, x δ etc. setzt, so ist klar, daß wenn man durch A1, A2 . . . Aµ die verschiedenen Formen bezeichnet,<br />

deren 1, 2, 3, 4 . . . n durch Verwechselung der Zeiger 1, 2, 3 . . . n fähig ist, die verschiedenen<br />

Werthe von v durch<br />

v<br />

� A1<br />

A1<br />

�<br />

, v<br />

� A1<br />

A2<br />

�<br />

, v<br />

� A1<br />

ausgedrückt werden können.” (N. H. <strong>Abel</strong>, 1826a, 74).<br />

29 (Wussing, 1969, 67).<br />

A3<br />

�<br />

. . . v<br />

Aµ<br />

� A1<br />

Aµ<br />

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!