05.01.2013 Views

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

8.2. Construction <strong>of</strong> the irreducible equation 169<br />

1<br />

µ<br />

be satisfied by all values <strong>of</strong> y which are obtained by attributing to y1<br />

1<br />

µ<br />

ωy1<br />

, ω2 1<br />

µ<br />

y1<br />

, . . . , ωn−1 1<br />

µ<br />

y<br />

all the values<br />

1 ”12 (see section 6.3.3). In 1826, it had been given no pro<strong>of</strong>, but<br />

in the notebook, ABEL provided the pro<strong>of</strong> as an easy and elegant application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fundamental concepts and tools.<br />

ABEL proceeded by establishing a central link between the irreducibility <strong>of</strong> φ (y, m) =<br />

0 and that <strong>of</strong> ∏ φ (y, m) = 0.<br />

<strong>The</strong>orem 11 If the equation<br />

is irreducible, then so is the equation<br />

φ (y, m) = 0<br />

φ1 (y, m) = ∏ φ (y, m) = 0. ✷<br />

ABEL argued for this theorem by a reductio ad absurdum pro<strong>of</strong> against which SYLOW<br />

later raised well founded objections. ABEL assumed that φ1 was reducible and that<br />

φ2 (y, m ′ ) was an irreducible 13 factor <strong>of</strong> ∏ φ (y, m) = 0. Under these assumptions,<br />

φ2 and φ would have a common root since all the roots <strong>of</strong> ∏ φ were also roots <strong>of</strong><br />

φ. <strong>The</strong> assumed irreducibility <strong>of</strong> φ then enabled ABEL to conclude that because the<br />

irreducible φ and φ2 had a root in common, φ would be a factor <strong>of</strong> φ2,<br />

φ2<br />

This in turn implied (by theorem 10)<br />

φ2<br />

� y, m ′ � = f (y, m) · φ (y, m) .<br />

� y, m ′ � = f1<br />

� ′′<br />

y, m � · ∏ φ (y, m) . (8.4)<br />

� �� �<br />

=φ1(y,m) On the other hand, φ2 had been assumed to be an irreducible factor <strong>of</strong> φ1 implying<br />

deg φ2 < deg φ1, which contradicted (8.4).<br />

SYLOW’S objections concerned the properties <strong>of</strong> ∏ φ. Besides certain points, at<br />

which ABEL left out assumptions <strong>of</strong> irreducibility, SYLOW noticed that ABEL tacitly<br />

assumed that φ (y, m) did not have factors in which all the coefficients were rational<br />

expressions in inner radicals and known quantities. If such factors were involved, the<br />

equation ∏ φ (y, m) = 0 might turn out to be a power <strong>of</strong> an irreducible equation. 14<br />

SYLOW repaired ABEL’S argument by refining his hierarchy <strong>of</strong> algebraic expressions.<br />

12 “[. . . ] so ist klar, daß der gegebenen Gleichung durch alle die Werthe von y genug werden muß,<br />

welche man findet, wenn man der Größe p 1 n alle die Werthe αp 1 n , α 2 p 1 n , . . . , α n−1 p 1 n beilegt.” (N. H.<br />

<strong>Abel</strong>, 1826a, 72).<br />

13 Actually, ABEL did not, presumably inadvertently, state the condition <strong>of</strong> irreducibility <strong>of</strong> φ2.<br />

14 (Sylow in N. H. <strong>Abel</strong>, 1881, vol. 2, 332).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!