05.01.2013 Views

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

RePoSS #11: The Mathematics of Niels Henrik Abel: Continuation ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

218 Chapter 11. CAUCHY’s new foundation for analysis<br />

For now, we have to stress the importance this theorem played in CAUCHY’S pro<strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the binomial theorem. <strong>The</strong> argument was, that since both the binomial (1 + x) m and<br />

the infinite power series (11.4) satisfied the same functional equation for all rational m,<br />

and since they were both continuous functions <strong>of</strong> m, they would coincide for all real<br />

values <strong>of</strong> m. Thus, CAUCHY proved the binomial theorem for all real exponents (here<br />

designated m).<br />

In CAUCHY’S theory <strong>of</strong> rigorously restructuring calculus, the binomial theorem<br />

played an extremely important role. 25 It provided one <strong>of</strong> the basic, theoretical bricks<br />

which could be used to rebuild the existing theory <strong>of</strong> real analysis. Historians have<br />

argued that CAUCHY’S rigorization and his pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the binomial theorem constitute<br />

a veiled attack on Fourier series. 26 However, although CAUCHY was critical toward<br />

J. B. J. FOURIER’S (1768–1830) reasoning, I find such a hypothesis largely unnecessary<br />

as CAUCHY’S rigorization program makes good sense from its own premises. 27<br />

11.6 Early reception <strong>of</strong> CAUCHY’s new rigor<br />

CAUCHY’S Cours d’analyse dealt exclusively with the theory functions from the per-<br />

spective <strong>of</strong> infinite series. Later in the 1820s, he also published lectures pertaining to<br />

rigorously founding the theory <strong>of</strong> differentiation and integration. 28<br />

As a textbook for the École Polytechnique, the Cours d’analyse was not successful.<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> internal animosities among the teachers, CAUCHY’S textbook was never<br />

used as a textbook but it may have served as inspiration for students preparing for<br />

the entrance exams <strong>of</strong> the school. Among his fellow mathematicians, CAUCHY’S pro-<br />

gram also received mixed reactions. In Germany, A. L. CRELLE (1780–1855) men-<br />

tioned CAUCHY’S textbooks in very positive terms, 29 and a German translation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Cours d’analyse appeared in 1828. 30 However, a distinct German reaction also existed<br />

which sought to continue the formal, algebraic approach to foundations <strong>of</strong> analysis in<br />

the so-called combinatorial school initiated by C. F. HINDENBURG (1741–1808), and M.<br />

OHM (1792–1872) pursued his own rigorization program. 31<br />

Thus, in the 1820s, the mathematical community could be divided into three camps<br />

reflecting their attitudes toward rigor:<br />

1. Some had picked up CAUCHY’S vision <strong>of</strong> a rigorization <strong>of</strong> analysis; both its<br />

theme and its tools. <strong>The</strong>y joined in the restriction to arithmetical equality and<br />

adopted CAUCHY’S redefinition <strong>of</strong> central concepts in terms <strong>of</strong> limits.<br />

25 (Grabiner, 1981b, 111).<br />

26 See e.g. (Bottazzini, 1986, 110).<br />

27 (Grabiner, 1981b, 111).<br />

28 (A.-L. Cauchy, 1823; A.-L. Cauchy, 1829).<br />

29 (Crelle, 1827; Crelle, 1828).<br />

30 (A. L. Cauchy, 1828).<br />

31 See (Jahnke, 1992).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!