01.02.2015 Views

69249454-chandler-semiotics

69249454-chandler-semiotics

69249454-chandler-semiotics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

180<br />

SEMIOTICS: THE BASICS<br />

print more than three centuries earlier. Michel de Montaigne wrote in<br />

1580: ‘Speaking is half his that speaks, and half his that hears; the last<br />

of which ought to prepare himself to receive it, according to its motion<br />

and rebound. Like tennis players, he that receives the ball, shifts and<br />

prepares, according as he sees him move who strikes the stroke, and<br />

according to the stroke it self’ (Essays, trans. Charles Cotton, 1685:<br />

‘Of experience’ III, 13). The anticipation involved is clearly ‘active’:<br />

you could never return a serve if you simply stood still waiting for the<br />

ball. Saussure’s ‘speech circuit’ was based on the notion that comprehension<br />

on the part of the listener is a kind of mirror of the speaker’s<br />

initial process of expressing a thought (ibid., 11–13; Harris 1987,<br />

22–5, 204–18). The shortcomings of this isomorphism would perhaps<br />

have been clearer if Saussure had been attempting to account for a<br />

broader range of forms of communication than speech alone. A<br />

dyslexic student once asked me, ‘Why is it so important to read so fast<br />

when the writer spent so long writing it’ The answer, of course, is<br />

that a significant part of the power of the written word lies in this asymmetry<br />

(for the shortcomings of the mirror model for the medium of<br />

film, see Larry Gross’s critique in Worth 1981, 9–11). Given the<br />

prominence of the concept of the code in Saussurean-inspired <strong>semiotics</strong>,<br />

it is also surprising that in Saussure’s model there is only the<br />

briefest of allusions to the speaker’s use of ‘the code provided by the<br />

language’, together with the implicit assumption that a fixed code is<br />

shared – a very monolithic conception (Saussure 1983, 14; Harris<br />

1987, 216, 230).<br />

In 1960 another structuralist linguist – Roman Jakobson<br />

(drawing on work by Bühler dating from the 1930s) – proposed a<br />

model of interpersonal verbal communication which moved beyond<br />

the basic transmission model of communication (see Figure 6.3;<br />

cf. Eco 1976, 141). Using the somewhat programmatic language<br />

mentioned earlier, Jakobson outlines what he regards as the six<br />

‘constitutive factors . . . in any act of verbal communication’ thus:<br />

The addresser sends a message to the addressee. To be operative<br />

the message requires a context referred to (‘referent’ in another,<br />

somewhat ambivalent, nomenclature), seizable by the<br />

addressee, and either verbal or capable of being verbalized, a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!