17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3. Preferences and decision making 115<br />

case we have to consider is the one in which only one person contributes.<br />

If this is person a, thefirst order condition in (3.29) holds for her. Person<br />

b spends all of his income on the private good, so that:<br />

u b Q<br />

u b q<br />

µ<br />

ˆQ,<br />

b Y<br />

≤<br />

p<br />

P<br />

p<br />

(3.32)<br />

with a strict inequality if the agent is not on the margin of contributing<br />

to the public good. In this case a redistribution of income from a to b will<br />

generally change the market demand since b will increase his demand for<br />

the private good and a generally will not change her demands to exactly<br />

offset these revisions. Thus we have market demands:<br />

ˆq = ˆq a b Y<br />

+<br />

p = ξa (P, p, Y a )+<br />

ˆQ = ˆ Q a = Ξ ¡ P, p, Y a ,Y b¢<br />

Y b<br />

p<br />

(3.33)<br />

In both cases, the non-cooperative procedure leads to an inefficient outcome<br />

(except for the cases in which one or the other has all of the income);<br />

this is the standard under-provision for the voluntary contributions public<br />

goods game. To see that for the case of an interior solution, add the two<br />

first order conditions (3.29), yielding<br />

u a Q<br />

u a q<br />

³<br />

ˆQ, a<br />

ˆq ´<br />

+ ubQ ub ³<br />

ˆQ, b<br />

ˆq<br />

q<br />

´<br />

=2 P<br />

p ,<br />

while Samuelson’s (1954) condition for an efficient allocation of public<br />

goodsrequiresthat<br />

u a Q<br />

u a q<br />

³<br />

ˆQ, a<br />

ˆq ´<br />

+ ubQ ub ³<br />

ˆQ, b<br />

ˆq<br />

q<br />

´<br />

= P<br />

. (3.34)<br />

p<br />

That is, the sum of the willingness to pay for the public good of the two<br />

partners, should equal to the opportunity cost of the public good in terms<br />

of the private good. In this regard, there is an under provision of the public<br />

good. 6<br />

We now present an example to illustrate some of the points made here.<br />

Normalize prices to unity, P = p =1, and take preferences represented by<br />

u a = q a Q α and u b = q b Q. The parameter α governs how much a likes the<br />

public good; if α>1 then she values it more than b if they have the same<br />

private consumption. We set Y a = ρ and Y b =(1− ρ) so that household<br />

6 Results on dynamic contributions games suggest that inefficiencies cam be eliminated<br />

if players contribute sequentially and cannot reduce previous contributions; see,<br />

for example, Matthews (2006).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!