17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

128 3. Preferences and decision making<br />

Stability and the Pareto weight<br />

In what follows, we concentrate on deterministic decision processes. Then<br />

the stability axiom has a very simple implication - namely that in program<br />

(3.37), the coefficient ūa is a well-defined function of prices, income<br />

and possibly distribution factors, denoted ūa (P, p,x,z). It follows that,<br />

for given fundamentals and price-income bundle, the outcome of the decision<br />

process is such that the utility of a is ūa (P, p,x,z), and that of b<br />

is Υ (P, p,x,ūa (P, p,x,z)). Note that under strict quasi-concavity, these<br />

utility levels are reached for only one consumption bundle.<br />

If, in addition, we adopt a strictly concave cardinalization of individual<br />

utilities, then the Pareto weight is also a well-defined function of prices,<br />

income and possibly distribution factors, denoted μ (P, p,x,z). For analytic<br />

tractability, we often add some structure to the problem by assuming that<br />

the function μ has convenient properties such as continuous differentiability.<br />

Such assumptions will be stated wherever they are needed.<br />

In summary: under our two assumptions of stability and efficiency, using<br />

a strictly concave cardinalization of preferences, the behavior of the<br />

household can be modelled in a simple way; that is, there exists a function<br />

μ (P, p,x,z) such that the household solves:<br />

max μ (P, p,x,z) u a ¡ Q, q a , q b¢ + u b ¡ Q, q a , q b¢<br />

under the budget constraint (3.38).<br />

3.5.5 Pareto weights and ‘power’<br />

(3.43)<br />

A major advantage of the formulation in (3.40) or (3.43) is that the Pareto<br />

weight has a natural interpretation in terms of respective decision powers.<br />

Thenotionof‘power’maybedifficult to define formally, even in a simplified<br />

framework like ours. Still, it seems natural to expect that when two people<br />

bargain, a person’s gain increases with the person’s power. This somewhat<br />

hazy notion is captured very effectively by the Pareto weights. Clearly, if<br />

μ in (3.40) is zero then it is as though b is a dictator, while if μ is large<br />

then a effectively gets her way. A key property of (3.40) is precisely that<br />

increasing μ will result in a move along the Pareto set, in the direction of<br />

higher utility for a (and lower for b). If we restrict ourselves to economic<br />

considerations, we may thus consider that the Pareto weight μ ‘reflects’ a’s<br />

power, in the sense that a larger μ corresponds to more power (and better<br />

outcomes) being enjoyed by a.<br />

The empirical implications of this remark are quite interesting. For instance,<br />

when a reform is known or predicted to improve the relative situation<br />

of a particular member (say, paying some family benefits to the<br />

wife instead of the husband), we should find that the reform increases the<br />

member’s Pareto weight. More generally, the intuitive idea that a specific<br />

distribution factor z is favorable to member a can readily be translated by

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!