17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

126 3. Preferences and decision making<br />

This setting generalizes Samuelson because the welfare index W depends<br />

on individual utilities, but also directly on prices, total expenditure and distribution<br />

factors. In other words, the household maximizes an index that is<br />

price (and income) dependent, which distinguishes this setting from a unitary<br />

representation. The surprising property is that under tsrict concavity<br />

one can assume without loss of generality that the index W is indeed linear<br />

(as in (3.40)). We shall come back to this issue below.<br />

Ordinal versus cardinal representation of preferences<br />

It is important to understand what, in the previous discussion, requires a<br />

cardinal representation of preferences, and what can be defined using only<br />

a standard, ordinal representation. The set of Pareto efficient allocations is<br />

an ordinal concept; it is not modified when us is replaced with F (us ) for a<br />

strictly increasing mapping F (.). Under smoothness conditions, the set is<br />

one-dimensional, and therefore can be described by one parameter. However,<br />

the parametrization entails cardinality issues. For instance, a natural<br />

parametrization is through the weight μ. Butμdepends on the particular<br />

cardinal representation that has been adopted for ua and ub :ifus is<br />

replaced with F (us ), then the parameter μ corresponding to a particular<br />

efficient allocation has to be modified accordingly. Moreover, the convexity<br />

properties of the Pareto set are also of a cardinal nature. Assuming<br />

smooth preferences, for any given price-income vector, one can find cardinal<br />

representations of preferences such that the Pareto frontier is convex,<br />

linear or concave. In most of what follows, we adopt the convention of always<br />

using a strictly concave representation of utilities. In this case, the<br />

Pareto set is strictly convex. Indeed, for a given price-income vector, take<br />

two points ¡ ūa , ūb¢ and ¡ u0a ,u0b¢ on the Pareto frontier, and let ¡ Q, qa , qb¢ and ¡ Q0 , q0a , q0b¢ be the corresponding consumption vectors. The vector<br />

¡ 00 00a 00b<br />

Q , q , q ¢ = 1 ¡ a b<br />

Q, q , q<br />

2<br />

¢ + 1 ¡ 0 0a 0b<br />

Q , q , q<br />

2<br />

¢<br />

satisfies the budget constraint, and by strict concavity,<br />

u s ¡ Q 00 , q 00a , q 00b¢ > 1<br />

2 us ¡ Q, q a , q b¢ + 1<br />

2 us ¡ Q 0 , q 0a , q 0b¢ = 1<br />

2 ūs + 1<br />

2 u0s<br />

for s = a, b. We conclude that the point 1<br />

2<br />

¡ ū a , ū b ¢ + 1<br />

2<br />

¡ u 0a ,u 0b ¢ belongs to<br />

the interior of the Pareto set.<br />

Graphically, on Figure 3.4, the Pareto set is indeed strictly convex. We<br />

seethatanypointontheUPFcanbedefined either by its coordinate on the<br />

horizontal axis, here u a , as in program (3.37), or by the negative of the slope<br />

of the Pareto frontier at that point, here μ as in program (3.40). Given that<br />

the UPF is strictly concave there is an increasing correspondence between<br />

ū a and μ: alargerū a (or μ) corresponds to an allocation that is more<br />

favorable to a (hence less favorable for a). Note that the correspondence

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!