17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

6. Uncertainty and Dynamics in the Collective model 263<br />

where K0 is a constant depending on the respective Pareto weights. In the<br />

end:<br />

l a = K 0 .w −γ<br />

2γ−1<br />

,c a = K 0 1−γ<br />

− 2γ−1<br />

.w<br />

and the indirect utility is of the form:<br />

a<br />

V a = K 00 .w<br />

1−γ<br />

− 2γ−1<br />

a<br />

for some constant K 00 . As expected, a is sheltered from non labor income<br />

risk by his risk sharing agreement with b. However, his consumption, labor<br />

supply and welfare fluctuate with his wage. The intuition is that that agents<br />

respond to price (or wage) variations by adjusting their demand (here labor<br />

supply) behavior in an optimal way. The maximization implicit in this<br />

process, in turn, introduces an element of convexity into the picture. 11<br />

6.3.4 Econometric issues<br />

Distributions versus realizations<br />

We now come back to the simpler, one-commodity framework. As expressed<br />

by Proposition 6.1, efficient risk sharing schemes satisfy the mutuality principle,<br />

which is a form of income pooling: the sharing rules depends only on<br />

total income, not on the agent’s respective contributions y a and y b per se.<br />

This result may sound surprising; after all, income pooling is a standard implication<br />

of the unitary setting which is typically not valid in the collective<br />

framework; moreover, it is regularly rejected empirically.<br />

The answer to this apparent puzzle relies on the crucial distinction between<br />

the (ex post) realization and the (ex ante) distribution of income<br />

shocks.Whenriskissharedefficiently, income realizations are pooled: my<br />

consumption should not suffer from my own bad luck, insofar as it does<br />

not affect aggregate resources. On the other hand, there exists a continuum<br />

of efficient allocations of resources, indexed by some Pareto weights;<br />

different weights correspond to different (contingent) consumptions. The<br />

Pareto weights, in turn, depend on the ex ante situations of the agents;<br />

for instance, if a has a much larger expected income, one can expect that<br />

her Pareto weight will be larger than b’s, resulting in a higher level of consumption.<br />

In other words, the pooling property does not apply to expected<br />

incomes, and in general to any feature (variance, skewness,...) of the probability<br />

distributions of individual income streams. The main intuition of the<br />

collective model is therefore maintained: power (as summarized by Pareto<br />

weights) matters for behavior - the nuance being that under efficient risk<br />

11 Generally, the ability of risk neutral agents to adjust actions after the state is observed<br />

induces a "risk loving" ingredient, whereby higher price variation is preferred,<br />

and which may counterweight the agent’s risk aversion.<br />

a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!