17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

118 3. Preferences and decision making<br />

³<br />

where e is an N-vector of ones. Let ˆQ s<br />

1, ... ˆ Qs ´<br />

N for s = a, b be a Nash<br />

equilibrium. 7 We say that person s contributes to good j if ˆ Q s j<br />

> 0. Let<br />

ma (respectively, mb ) be the number of goods to which a (respectively, b)<br />

contributes. Browning at al (2010) show that if all public goods are bought<br />

( ˆ Qs j > 0 for at least one s) theneitherma + mb = N or ma + mb = N +1<br />

(generally). This striking result shows that there is at most one public good<br />

to which both partners contribute. 8<br />

To see the result informally, suppose that both partners simultaneously<br />

contribute to two public goods, i and j. Then both set the marginal rates<br />

of substitution between the two goods to unity (the relative prices) and<br />

hence equalize the mrs’s:<br />

ua i<br />

ua j<br />

= ub i<br />

u b j<br />

(3.36)<br />

Without restrictions on preferences and incomes, this is unlikely to hold.<br />

Moreover, if it does hold, if we make an infinitesimal change in Y a or Y b<br />

the property (3.36) will generally not hold.<br />

If there is some overlap in contributions (ma + mb = N +1)thenwe<br />

have the local income pooling result, just as in the one public good case<br />

when both contribute. The result that each partner has a set of public<br />

goods which are his or her ‘domain’ suggests a gender division of allocation<br />

within the household. Note, however, that the goods that each takes as<br />

their domain is determined endogenously by preferences and the division<br />

of income within the household. As we move from b having all the income<br />

to a having all the income (holding total income constant) the number of<br />

goods that she contributes to will generally rise and the number of goods<br />

to which he contributes will generally fall.<br />

We illustrate with an example with egoistic preferences from Browning<br />

et al (2010) for the case of two public goods, G and H. Let the two partners<br />

have preferences represented by the pair of Cobb-Douglas utility functions<br />

u a (q a ,G,H) = lnq a + 5 8<br />

ln G +<br />

3 9 H<br />

u b (q b ,G,H) = lnq b + 15 1<br />

ln G + ln H<br />

32 2<br />

The relative weights on the two public goods are 45 15<br />

24 and 16 for a and<br />

b respectively; that is, a likes good G relative to good H, morethanb.<br />

Figure 3.3 shows the purchases of public goods against a’s share of income.<br />

When a has a low share of income (region I on the x-axis) she does not<br />

7 We assume enough to ensure the existence of at least one Nash equilibrium. We do<br />

not impose uniqueness.<br />

8 This result is generic in the sense that it is possible to find ‘knife-edge’ configurations<br />

of preferences and incomes for which the two partners contribute to more than one<br />

common public good.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!