17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

266 6. Uncertainty and Dynamics in the Collective model<br />

general population), theory 13 suggests that the matching should actually<br />

be negative assortative (that is, more risk averse agents should be matched<br />

with less risk averse ones) - so that heterogeneity should be, if anything,<br />

larger within risk sharing groups than in the general population. 14<br />

Finally, can we test for efficient risk sharing without this assumption?<br />

The answer is yes; such a test is developed for instance in <strong>Chiappori</strong>,<br />

Townsend and Yamada (2008) and in <strong>Chiappori</strong>, Samphantharak, Schulhofer-<br />

Wohl and Townsend (2010). However, it requires long panels - since one<br />

must be able to disentangle the respective impacts of income distributions<br />

and realizations.<br />

6.4 Intertemporal Behavior<br />

6.4.1 The unitary approach: Euler equations at the household<br />

level<br />

We now extend the model to take into account the dynamics of the relationships<br />

under consideration. Throughout this section, we assume that<br />

preferences are time separable and of the expected utility type. The first<br />

contributions extending the collective model to an intertemporal setting<br />

are due to Mazzocco (2004, 2007); our presentation follows his approach.<br />

Throughout this section, the household consists of two egoistic agents who<br />

live for T periods. In each period t ∈ {1, ..., T }, lety i t denote the income of<br />

member i.<br />

We start with the case of a unique commodity which is privately consumed;<br />

c i t denotes member i’s consumption at date t and pt is the corresponding<br />

price. The household can save by using a risk-free asset; let<br />

st denotes the net level of (aggregate) savings at date t, andRt its gross<br />

return. Note that, in general, y i t, st and c i t are random variables<br />

We start with the standard representation of household dynamics, based<br />

on a unitary framework. Assume, therefore, that there exists a utility function<br />

u ¡ c a ,c b¢ representing the household’s preferences. The program de-<br />

13 See, for instance <strong>Chiappori</strong> and Reny (2007).<br />

14 An alternative test relies on the assumption that agents have CARA preferences.<br />

Then, as seen above, the sharing rule is an affine function, in which only the intercept<br />

depends on Pareto weights (the slope is determined by respective risk tolerances). It<br />

follows that variations in levels of individual consumptions are proportional to variations<br />

in total income, the coefficient being independent of Pareto weights. The very nice<br />

feature of this solution, adopted for instance by Townsend (1994), is that it is compatible<br />

with any level of heterogeneity in risk aversion. Its main drawback is that the<br />

CARA assumption is largely counterfactual; empirical evidence suggests that absolute<br />

risk aversion decreases with wealth.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!