17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3. Preferences and decision making 127<br />

between ū a and μ is one-to-one; that is, for any ū a , there exists exactly<br />

one μ that picks up the efficient point providing a with exactly ū a ,and<br />

conversely for any μ there is only one allocation that maximizes (3.40)<br />

under budget constraint, therefore only one corresponding utility level ū a .<br />

We can also understand from Figure 3.5 why the maximization of generalized<br />

Samuelson index W ¡ u a ,u b , P, p,x, z ¢ is equivalent to that of a<br />

linear combination μu a + u b . The maximization of a non linear index W<br />

will select a point where the Pareto frontier is tangent to some indifference<br />

curve of W .If−μ denotes the slope of the corresponding tangent, maximizing<br />

μu a + u b leads to exactly the same point. Replacing W with its linear<br />

equivalent can be done at any point, provided that μ varies adequately;<br />

technically, this simply requires that:<br />

μ = ∂W/∂ua<br />

∂W/∂u b<br />

The main drawback of the generalized index version is that a continuum<br />

of different welfare indices lead to the same choices. Indeed, for any<br />

function F strictly increasing in its first argument, the indices W and<br />

¯W = F (W, P, p,x, z) are empirically indistinguishable. The linear version,<br />

from this perspective, has an obvious advantage in terms of parsimony; in<br />

addition, it has a natural interpretation in terms of distribution of powers<br />

(see below).<br />

Finally, we may briefly discuss two particular cases. One obtains when<br />

the cardinal representations of utilities are concave but not strictly concave.<br />

In that case, the UPF may include ‘flat’ (that is, linear) segments (Figure<br />

3.6). Then Program (3.37) is still equivalent to Program (3.40), but the<br />

relationship between ū a and μ is no longer one-to-one. It is still the case<br />

that for any ū a ,exactlyoneμ picks up the efficient point providing a with<br />

ū a . But the converse property does not hold; that is, to some values of μ are<br />

associated a continuum of utility levels ū a ; graphically, this occurs when −μ<br />

is exactly the slope of a flat portion of the UPF. 13 This case is particularly<br />

relevant for two types of situations, namely transferable utility on the one<br />

hand (then the cardinalization is usually chosen so that the entire UPF is<br />

a straight line) and explicit randomization on the other hand.<br />

The second particular case relates to local non differentiability of utility<br />

functions (Figure 3.7). Then the UPF may exhibit a kink, and the one-toone<br />

relationship breaks down for the opposite reason - namely, many values<br />

of μ are associated with the same ū a .<br />

13However, a strictly quasi concave generalized welfare index would still pick up exactly<br />

one point.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!