17.01.2013 Views

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

Pierre André Chiappori (Columbia) "Family Economics" - Cemmap

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

3. Preferences and decision making 125<br />

all allocations providing a with exactly ū a ,theefficient one(s) generate the<br />

maximum possible utility for b. It goes without saying that this approach<br />

- just like most microeconomics - should not be taken literally. No one<br />

believes that agents actually write and solve a program such as (3.37). Our<br />

claim is simply that when a decision process, whatever its exact nature,<br />

always lead to efficient outcomes, then for any choice of prices, income and<br />

distribution factors there exists a ū a such that the household behaves as if<br />

it was solving program (3.37).<br />

The solution to (3.37), when it exists (that is, if ū a is feasible), depends on<br />

prices, total expenditure and on the arbitrary level ū a ; it can be denoted<br />

as u b = Υ (P, p,x,ū a ). The set of all pairs (ū a , Υ (P, p,x,ū a )) when ū a<br />

varies over a domain of feasible allocations for a is the set of all efficient<br />

allocations; it is known as the Pareto frontier or utility possibility frontier,<br />

UPF. Under the assumption that the utility functions are strictly concave<br />

it is straight forward to show that the function Υ (.) is strictly concave in<br />

ū a (see below). This allows us to write Program (3.37) in a different but<br />

equivalent way. Let μ denote the Lagrange multiplier for constraint (3.39);<br />

note that μ is always nonnegative (and is a function of (P, p,x, z)). Then<br />

the program is equivalent to:<br />

max<br />

Q,qa ,qb μu a ¡ Q, q a , q b¢ + u b ¡ Q, q a , q b¢<br />

(3.40)<br />

under the constraint (3.38). The coefficient μ is known as the Pareto weight<br />

for a. Thatis,aParetoefficient outcome always maximizes a weighted sum<br />

of the two individual utilities. A slightly modified form that keeps the<br />

formal symmetry of the problem is sometimes used:<br />

max<br />

Q,qa ,qb ˜μu a ¡ Q, q a , q b¢ +(1− ˜μ) u b ¡ Q, q a , q b¢ , (3.41)<br />

where ˜μ ∈ [0, 1]. The Pareto weight plays a critical role in all that follows.<br />

Finally, an equivalent formulation directly generalizes Samuelson’s household<br />

welfare. Specifically, take any smooth function W ¡ ua ,ub , P, p,x, z ¢<br />

that is strictly increasing in its first two arguments, and consider the program:<br />

max<br />

Q,qa ,qb W ¡ u a ¡ Q, q a , q b¢ ,u b ¡ Q, q a , q b¢ , P, p,x, z ¢<br />

(3.42)<br />

under the constraint (3.38). Clearly, a solution to (3.42) is Pareto efficient;<br />

for otherwise some alternative allocation would increase both u a and u b ,<br />

one of them (at least) strictly, but that would strictly increase W ,acontradiction.<br />

Conversely, any allocation that is Pareto efficient maximizes a<br />

weighted sum of the form (3.40), which is a particular (linear) case of a<br />

W function. This establishes equivalence: an allocation is Pareto efficient if<br />

and only if there exists some W such that it maximizes (3.42) under budget<br />

constraint.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!